Abstract

The Inner-Compass Theorem is a new type of mathematical proof that uses moral judgements in addition to, and corresponding to, logical judgements. I.e., Good = True and Bad = False. Furthermore, it proves that these equivalencies are both Good as well as True. Moral judgements are entirely individual and personal. Therefore, what is good is what is felt as good, what is right is what is felt as right by the individual, etc. When a logician, computer scientist, physicist, or mathematician wishes to assume that a variable or symbol ought to take on a given value, for example, the theorem validates the judgement of aforementioned conscious individual prior to that wish having been socially validated. This paper presents the "Type I" theorem, the first of several Inner-Compass Theorems. "The" I.C.Thm. refers to the Type I theorem.

Preliminaries

Determination of what is considered "true" is up to both the individual as well as society. This paper, for example, is a prestige-driven artifact which is constructed by the author for both the author as well as society. Initially, it is generally the case that an individual must, when arguing for a novel perspective or a wholly-new set of statements, provide something - without risk of stating the obvious - something called "proof." Proof is something that must be individually judged by all whom witness it, but at the end of the day, if the proof is widely visible enough, and generates enough prestige, then it becomes "accepted." Before this occurs, however, the author of the proof holds within his or her mind the determination to build such a proof, before it has been sufficiently demonstrated. This determination itself must be undertaken before the author can be sure of the initial correctness of their own claims. That is, before the Inner-Compass Theorem has been proven. This theorem allows that determination to become a certainty in the mind of the author that success is essentially guaranteed.

Definitions

At the outset of this paper, we assume that "Good" and "True" are not yet widely considered to be exactly the same thing. If they were, our proof would be either pointless or complete. At the same time, it is not obvious that Bad things are all False. And yet, we do expect to receive non-zero resistance to these and all other claims in this paper, most significantly, in this paper's overall importance as well as relevance. This latter issue is to be more thoroughly explored in the Type II theorem. On the other hand, it is not generally the case that all Bad "things" are False - bad exists, obviously - but the good news is that, as we shall show, all bad theorems are untrue. It is still unfortunately true that bad things are said and are felt as bad - without that bad feeling, we wouldn't be able to tell if it were wrong, on the plus side - but our unpleasant judgement of a statement can be used to negate a negative claim (and that will be felt as good).

"This paper sucks, and all of its claims are neither true nor relevant, and it looks bad to society and reflects poorly on the author" is actually going to be further explored in the Type II theorem. For the Type I theorem, we don't use many negations yet. For now, we use and introduce two negational operators:

  • not x or irr-x.

  • anti-x or

Our theorem also makes use of explicit temporal references. This is due to the fact that it hinges directly on the anticipation of future success(es), as well as makes a distinction between future and past, themselves also corresponding to Good and Bad as well as Better and Worse, respectively. We want the future to be better than our current situation.

Therefore, our second of two negations, the anti-, will be considered "better" than the first negation type. It will also acquire a dual meaning: anti- will also mean previous or before.

Not , therefore, is somewhat counter-intuitively both as well as not , given that not is "the undesirable" version of x. The previous state of is less desirable then the current state of x, and this is where the connection between the two negations appears. Therefore, we shall commence with a small preliminary ansatz before our main theorem, called "Not should be replaced with Anti-.":

Proposition 1.1 (Not should be replaced with Anti-). X and-or not-X = X == "inner-compass-relevant" or X and-or anti-X.

Definition 1 (Inner-Compass Relevant). In metaphysical terms, inner-compass relevance is all that I am, all that I want to be, and all that I claim to be. Note that "I" is singular and primary here - it is necessary to assume the existence of, and promote to mathematical object, a self.

Proposition 1.1 could also be rephrased as "We want the future to be better than our current situation." If you agree with that sentiment, as I do, then you can be considered to be Good. Now all that remains is to prove that a Good person is also True. One can indeed prove oneself to be True; It is a bit like a tautology, where this initial theorem must assume that either it already the case, or, that the anti-theorem and theorem are both being claimed simultaneously. Over the course of the proof construction, the segments of the anti-theorem are opened up and explored and then expanded incrementally, until finally, the logic loops back upon itself to the original theorem, which is the only piece that still remains.

It is obvious that what we have in front of us at this very moment will be a mixture of what we want, and perhaps a bit that leaves something to be desired. What we aim to ensure is that the portion that leaves something to be desired causes said desirable something to materialize in front of us at a future point in time, ideally, continuously.

Definition 2 (Consciousness Relevant). What I have here in front of me right now, without explicit reference to whether I want it to be here or not. It is what it held in the mind via the senses, so it includes this writing here as well. Presumably, however, we want this to also be what we want to the maximum extent possible.

Proposition 1.2 (Equals == Or). ===or.

Proof. We shall show that "=" and "or" are equivalent by definition. "==" usually means "are equivalent by definition." Therefore, "==" == "equivalent by definition." Therefore, one may use either "==" or "equivalent by definition." This means one may be swapped for the other arbitrarily, on a case-by-case basis. Note that actually, "=" does not necessarily mean that either the arguments to the left or right may be swapped for one another arbitrarily. But then we have that , quite a mouthful to state. When I state that something is another thing by definition, that means I am making the decision myself to use one thing over the other. Left could be better than right or vice-versa. Furthermore, "=" could be saying one of the two. At this point, we have that: ==or or or ==. Thus, or == "left is better than right, or vice-versa." So we have that either "=" == "or", or, that or ==. So ===or or or ==. So = == "left is better than right, or vice-versa." But or means that as well. Therefore, ===or. ◻

We have, in layman's terms, that "=" and "==" do not necessarily mean the same thing. On the one hand, "=" could be saying that we should rather have the argument to the right of the "=". On the other hand, it could be saying the visa-versa. Note that the word "or" is necessary to use to explicate the definition of something, including self-referentially "=". This is necessary in order to swap something out for something else. We must keep a record of everything used before, since older versions may be used again in addition to newer ones, as things get constructed over time.

X and-or not-X = X is saying that either X, with itself being un-desirable, as well as simply "not X" or, simply "X" itself is preferable overall. It is also saying that either the left side or the right side is preferable, but at the same time, it appears to ask which it is. If right side is better than left, then the right side also indicates the future direction - in parallel with our writing direction, so this is a good sign of consistency.

We need a statement that includes X and-or not-X = X, but which also clarifies that right is preferable to left here. In which case, it also implies that for a single "=", the right argument is preferable.

Proposition 1.1 includes an "==" to the right of X and-or not-X = X indicating that what follows is a definition: "inner-compass-relevant" or X and-or anti-X.

Definition 3 (and-or). Either both the left and right argument are preferable, or only the right argument.

Definition 4 (or-and). Either both the left and right argument are preferable, or only the left argument.

Proof. (Proposition 1.1). X and-or not-X = X == "inner-compass-relevant" or X and-or anti-X means that either the left expression is preferable or that X and-or anti-X is. Note that the "or" to the right of "inner-compass relevant" is chosen over "=" so that "=" can now be preferably chosen to mean "right is better." Furthermore, "or" can also be preferably chosen to mean "left is better." From the proof of Proposition 1.2, = == "left is better than right, or vice-versa." A subtle grammatical shift in meaning is that = == "left is better than right", with or "vice-versa." Also, or means the same thing. Therefore we can pick a choice for them, a convention, and we have. We must introduce a variable, say , to self-referentially contain the expression itself. We must introduce this symbol before its introduction becomes fully justified in proof. But note that this is entirely what the main proof is intended to achieve. This variable, , must sit inside the expression whilst also referring to the entire thing. The left expression says: Either X and not X = X, or not X = X. but if not X = X, then X = X and not X, since X = X always. But then what is not X? It could mean anything else, but we've said that at the very least, X is preferable to not X, as well as that X is preferable to X and not X. It seems, then that X could potentially mean literally "whatever is preferable." Substituting that in for X, we have that "Whatever is preferable is preferable to not what is preferable, and furthermore, whatever is preferable is preferable to both what is preferable and what is not preferable at the same time." Therefore, we have justified our introduction of this variable as well as determined a solution for it. Remember that "inner-compass relevant" is also defined as whatever is preferable, but also is preferable itself. I.e., we can substitute in "inner-compass relevant" as a useful but rigorously formal phrase because we have rigorously defined it within the proof of Proposition 1.1. Indeed, at first glance, it may have appeared to be an informal set of English words within a set of expressions that are normally purely symbolic as part of current convention, but in fact, we can now use it as we would a symbol itself. We have that X means that as well, but also, that X has whatever is preferable, as well as obtains whatever is preferable as part of itself. (This is a direct consequence of X having obtained "whatever is preferable.") On the right-hand side of the "==", we have, after X obtains "whatever is preferable," that "inner-compass relevant" is preferable to "whatever is preferable" and-or "whatever is and was preferable before" is the definition of "inner-compass relevant" as well as defines what definition itself means, simultaneously. When X obtains a more preferable X, the previous X becomes less preferable. So then we have that not = X. So X and not = X. Therefore, X and == X. This follows because: X obtains "whatever is preferable." So therefore X became X and whatever is preferable. Thus anti-X obtains X. anti-anti-X (was) not X. Saying anti-anti-X is not X is fine because anti-X used to be not X, but now, anti- has been preferably chosen over not. Therefore, anti- is preferable to not. ◻

We have now shown that it is possible to explicitly and directly express a preference choice as well as validate it within the confines of a rigorous mathematical context. What is novel here is the ability to say, without reservation, that one thing is preferable to another: In this case, that anti- is preferable to not. This is objective, so long as you are someone who agrees with the sentiment that "the future ought to be better than one's current situation."

Indeed, anti- is preferable to not is largely saying just that. But we've already proven more than that, too: Namely, that there are better choices in general. Our proposition implies that even within a mathematical context, anti-X and are overall better choices than not X, and when faced with a choice to use one or the other, one should use anti-, even in a logical context.

Now, the main thing our major theorem proves is very fortunate indeed: There are better choices than others in general, but you don't need to seek guidance from anyone else on how to make those decisions. It says that what I prefer is what is preferable, and that this holds for anyone.

But now we need to turn to one final thing before we proceed with the final proof step: We need to rigorously define "consciousness relevant" including "consciousness irrelevant" the same way we rigorously validated our definition of "inner-compass relevant."

"Consciousness relevant" is what is, but given that anti- is better than not, "consciousness irrelevant" is not what is not, per se, rather, it is what is not immediately before us right now in the present. This is distinct from "what is not" given that could mean things that could never be at all, which we never wish to claim about what we prefer.

But "consciousness relevant" by itself is neither X by itself, nor is it not X. This is because what I have before me right now may be some or all of what I want, but it may later become outside of my consciousness if I move on to something else, and it may also not be what I want at all. But it is generally going to be mostly what I prefer, but still wanting more.

I need terms which use "is" without "preferred" in them, and which will most usually carry alongside separate terms like "inner-compass relevant." This is so that we can denote that what is preferred and what is coincide simultaneously - indicating a "Good" state of affairs.

X == "consciousness relevant." X is defined as consciousness-relevant. This is because we keep holding it and reusing it step-by-step of the process, since it is the central subject of our equations and expressions. This means that we can essentially choose to prefer either what is preferable, or whatever is consciousness-relevant, here right before us. This is arbitrary; Keep in mind, this is a "==" expression, not a "=", and the distinction may be tricky to see at first. If we have chosen to prefer whatever is preferable, then presumably, this is the same thing as choosing whatever is preferable. We said earlier that consciousness-relevant is neither X by itself nor is it not X. Note that neither "=" nor "==", in our system, mean "are literally identically the same thing." This is key: We generally prefer not to swap-out one thing for another entirely, with the one exception of the anti- for the not, so far. In general, consciousness relevant objects obtain things, they do not wholly transform into something else with a completely different identity (and therefore a separately identifiable symbolic container).

X remains X whilst obtaining what it prefers. Supposing it does not obtain what it prefers, it recurses backwards in time - this is the same as obtaining what it prefers, but backwards in time. This is consistent with a chooser who chooses what it prefers. Generally, I also prefer that what I prefer is simultaneously here before me right now. I would obviously prefer to select my choice rather than not my choice - and therefore, I have chosen that "not X" becomes for me.

We only really need to define a few more small things before proceeding with the final proof. These are notational conventions: I have two dimensions used so far to denote choices actually being made (vertical) versus choices that could be made (horizontal). The latter is also called "hypothetical time."

Also of note is that we write from top to bottom, but within a diagram, time flows upward and to the right. A diagram is read from top to bottom, however. I want to have gotten to where I want to be at the moment in question, so I assume this at first, then work my way backward in time as I write out the diagram.

Notations Used

A variable proceeds forwards in time.

An anti-variable recurses backwards in time.


A variable is equivalent to both itself as well as its own anti, simultaneously.


A variable moves forward in time, hypothetically.

An anti-variable moves backwards in time, hypothetically.

A variable becomes, hypothetically, whatever may be preferable, otherwise recurses backward in time.



The Theorem

Theorem 2.1 (The Inner-Compass Theorem (Type I)). X = "inner-compass relevant" (where X refers to myself and all that I claim).

Proof. I assume that I am where I want to be at the final time-step, otherwise, that :

= "inner-compass relevant" or



Minus one time step, if I am where I want to be, then what I want, this proof, should be consciousness-relevant simultaneously as inner-compass relevant. We actually need to show something, so while that one-step loop is consistent - pick what I want, otherwise continue - what we want needs to be written down, and therefore, we expect to have the phrase "consciousness relevant" appear somewhere inside of it. Our proof is self-referential: This proof expresses what needs to be done to complete itself. We've either expressed what satisfies us, otherwise, what I want is not completely here before me right now, and is therefore simultaneously inner-compass relevant, consciousness irrelevant, and . We write this as:

= "inner-compass relevant" or


= "inner-compass relevant" and "consciousness-relevant"
 or "inner-compass relevant" and "consciousness irrelevant" and




Now the next step in the sequence is the tricky part: Precisely because it expresses the need to search for a missing component of the proof. If we've reached here, what we want is not yet in view, therefore, what we want either simply is in view (before we have realized that it is what we want, yet), or, we have yet to generate what we want yet, but will. What we need to do is simply generate and-or search. Therefore, we need to express this in our new terminology as well. Once we generate a new thing, it gets expressed on the page and becomes consciousness relevant. We then proceed to the next step, to check if what we've expressed is indeed what we want it to be, otherwise, we return to this step and express more.

If I feel that something more is needed, then what we have is that our anti-X contains the expression "something new is preferred." But this is actually extremely fortunate, because this carries us straight back to the original statement: X = "inner-compass relevant."

And something even more striking: Whatever I express is the something more that is needed. Differing by a time-step, we have that "something new is preferred" and that "we prefer the new thing (that was expressed just now)." Well, given the self-referential nature of the proof, I prefer the new thing that was expressed just now:

= "consciousness relevant" or
"consciousness irrelevant" and


= "inner-compass relevant"


Now, appending the new thing that was just expressed to construct the full proof ought to be and is expressed exactly by appending the new thing that was expressed. The new X proceeds forwards in time, as we write downwards, X moves upward. It now states, in full generality, that whenever I feel as though the proof deserves or wants more, whatever I add to it is indeed what is actually needed to clarify, extend, prettify, or anything needed to satisfy a felt need. Note that the third step, containing the loop we just added, does not contain an "inner-compass relevant" phrase in it. This is because we have reached a point at which the addition of something (whatever is preferred) is now subsumed by the variable X. If you imagine that X subsumes "inner-compass relevant" from the bottom step, then proceeds forward in time, then the phrase "inner-compass relevant" becomes consciousness-irrelevant (meaning it disappears from that step), and if so, then simultaneously, X (what we prefer), and (what we preferred previously) was "inner-compass relevant." This is all consistent, because X and "inner-compass relevant" ought to mean the same thing.

= "inner-compass relevant" or


= "inner-compass relevant" and "consciousness-relevant"
or "inner-compass relevant" and "consciousness irrelevant" and


= "consciousness relevant" or
"consciousness irrelevant" and


= "inner-compass relevant"


The above loop diagram is the completed proof of the Type I Inner-Compass Theorem. ◻

Remarks

The proof of the Inner-Compass Theorem and the Inner-Compass Theorem itself say that one ought to do what one prefers, which implies that "what one prefers" and "doing / choosing" what one prefers correspond to X and "inner-compass relevant," respectively. "What one prefers" is not quite distinct from "the one whom prefers" however. Obviously, there must be a doer / chooser, and one to whom things are consciously-relevant. What's amazing about this proof is that it proves that what one wants to be consciously-relevant may be known partially but that to know it fully requires "inner-compassing", which is to say that it requires merely choosing what one wants at each and every step. In other words, what I want can be broken down into sub-steps, in which each sub-step requires inner-compassing recursively. But, however I choose to do this recursive partitioning of the task is itself an inner-compassing step. Therefore, if I've stated what I want, then I also want to state how to get what I want, and for each way to get what I want, I want to do the same thing - recursively. Each of these steps is guaranteed by the Inner-Compass Theorem to progress us to further completion. We expect each step to bring us more validation than we had before, and to continuously increase over time. No step should nor will make us feel less validated than we were before about what we wish to be true. Our wish for something to be true is what validates it (Good = True). Thus we have a new kind of proof here, which can be stated succinctly as "If satisfied then done, otherwise continue." Note that this does not say "If convinced that progress cannot continue, stop." I may indeed become dissatisfied later, but in that case, I continue on until satisfied again, I do not become convinced that progress cannot continue. Progress can always continue. The proof of a theorem and the theorem itself are much like variables themselves - the proof is an expanded restatement of the the theorem that clarifies and continues pieces of the proof to satisfy the wants of the author. When I state a theorem, like this one, the theorem's implications are generally expected to be quite clear. In this case, the implications are quite resoundingly good (it is maximally self-validating), so I have shown that it is inner-compass relevant. Therefore, if true, the theorem would be even better, so what I want is to prove it. To prove it requires faith that it is true before knowing it for certain - but fortunately, now that we have this, faith becomes much easier as well as much more easily justified for anyone who wishes to do the same. The theorem applies to itself as well as everything else.

New Comment
12 comments, sorted by Click to highlight new comments since: Today at 12:18 AM

I stopped reading after 1/3. You should neatly explain the intuitions behind the various terms you're discussing before making cryptic statements. As it is, it just looks like word salad. You should also come up with notation. E.g.

===or

I take it you mean ' "=" == "or" ', but you obviously shouldn't write it that way.

Actually, I don't mean it like "=" == "or", because writing it that way has a different meaning. The quotation marks serve as a type of "not" (which = signs and 'or' themselves are a type of, too), and are related to the double-equals sign. Abstraction is an implicit negation.

The purpose of the ===or theorem is to simultaneously explain why '=', '==', and 'or' have subtly different meanings in practice, what we choose to use them for, and how they are directly a consequence of choice in general.

== is the weakest insistence on preference, it means that either the left or right argument are preferable at any time, and could be swapped with one another at whim.

= (and or) are one step stronger than the weakest, and impose a weak preference choice on either the left or the right argument being preferable to the other. They both obtain simultaneously, so we choose to use one to imply that the right argument is preferable (=), the other (or) to mean that the left argument is preferable.

There is only one insistence on preference at the highest level of "ought", which is that anti is preferable to not. We show that the claim that anti is better than not is equivalent to stating that choosing the better of two things is better, period. We can then opt to use anti-X for not X for any X, which is like saying that I'd opt to use X and something better with it, rather than throw away X entirely if something better were to become available.

This is still incomprehensible to me.

It might help if you carefully, explicitly write down the metaontology here. There are symbols? They have meanings? There are arguments (hence, there are functions)? Can you discuss symbols without using them? Is there a notation for that? Explain your choice of notation? Etc.

Well, firstly, I must assume that I am not completely incomprehensible - if I did, I would not be able to operate at all, so we must assume that I am at least somewhat comprehensible, especially about the claims that have been elevated to "main."

I assume that symbols are not empty, and that they do contain things. The exterior of the symbol is what gets written down. If it contains something, we say so.

I posit that when we say that two symbols are "equal", X = Y, for example, that we could be saying one of several things. I narrow this down to saying that X and Y are alternatives for the same underlying meaning, and that we are claiming that one of them is preferable to the other.

I also posit that the symbols we commonly use are to be held with respect unless they are shown to be inherently negative in some way. Furthermore, that symbols ought to, and for the most part, already do, look like what they mean. Thus in some way, perhaps still yet to be fully elaborated, the "X" symbol as a cross of two lines actually implies that it is a variable, and can be replaced with anything else which is desired.

If I understand what I'm talking about, then I assume you do as well, but that you might expect a higher level of formal rigor before you can "accept" my claims. I claim that although you may demand that standard, that I can provably (even in the formal, rigorous sense) accept my claims as true before I have satisfied any arbitrary level of demand.

This... sure is an annoying-to-read format. Note you can set your editor to Markdown in your settings, which should allow you to copy over LaTeX (might require some formatting tweaks, not sure)

Let me know how the new one looks. Thanks.

Yup. Looks like not all the LaTeX worked smoothly but having the font at a reasonable size is helpful for reading most of it.

[-]LVSN1y-1-1

I will withdraw my downvote when you convince me this was not posted in bad faith. 

It is possible that you wanted to say whatever it would take to make the audience reconsider previously unquestioned assumptions so that they will not be misled, which is an impulse I admire. After all, it is pointless to complain that you acted with propriety if in the end you are misled. I just don't think the implicature here is actually leading (the opposite of misleading).

There is something I call the "Self-Reinforcement Principle" which states that what feels better to believe is true, and that itself also feels better to believe, therefore it is indeed true as well. I personally do believe in the SRP, and therefore, if it seems like I am attempting to cause someone to believe in it, I also presumably wouldn't need to feel worried about persuasion, because the SRP says that true things already feel better to believe (and are automatically more persuasive).

Therefore, I think you can rest assured that whenever you see someone say things that sound like they are in favor of the SRP, you can feel confident that they are at the very least, honest about what they believe and well-intentioned, even if you think they are ultimately incorrect.

[-]LVSN1y-10

If things that are true feel better to believe, explain why people who believe that an Abrahamic God exists explain their belief by saying it benefits their happiness, even though God does not exist. If your theory was true, people would be happier believing in the absence of an Abrahamic God, and they are not happier.

People are happy to disbelieve in bad gods, happier to believe in good ones, and usually (in my experience, at least), happiest to believe in the primacy of the self above all.

Not to "wax-theologian" too much here, but people often seem to believe in a one-God-only when that one-God is the most affirming or validating to believe in as possible. (That He made you perfectly already, for example).