The core of this post seems to be this
As Zack_M_Davis points out in his review, one of the issues with this definition is that there are infinite variations of "context" that can be added in any given situation "I'm wearing a hat while saying this", and there are infinite implications that any given thing you say can have "this implies that the speaker has a mouth and could therefore say the thing.
However, I do think that there is an actual, useful, real distinction here that's both important and doesn't have another thing to describe. The thing I think this is pointing at is "How much you and others are willing to think about the consequences of what is said seperate from its' truth value."
This split is quite important in a community that cares strongly about truth, and strongly about the outcomes of the world, and being able to say "we're in a decoupling space" or "this is a contextualzing conversation" or "I generally support decoupling as an epistemic norm" is quite an important shorthand to point at that thing.
I'd love to see the post cleaned up to make it clear that you're talking about "contextualizing as understanding how your words will have an effect in the context that you're in" and decoupling as "decoupling what you say from the effects it may create."
It occurs to me that "free speech", "heterodoxy", and "decoupling vs contextualising" are all related to intelligence vs virtue signaling. In particular, if you want to do or see more intelligence signaling, then you should support free speech and decoupling norms. If you want to do or see more virtue signaling, then you should support contextualising norms and restrictions on free speech. Heterodox ideas tend to be better (more useful) for intelligence signaling and orthodox ideas better for virtue signaling. (Hopefully this is obvious once pointed out, but I can explain more if not.)
Decoupling, orthogonality, unbundling, separation of concerns, relevance, the belief that the genetic fallacy is in fact a fallacy, hugging the query.... :)
Not a new idea, but an important one, and worth writing explicitly about!
Question: is there any reason to use the words "decoupling" rather than "coupling"? It seems to me that "low decoupling" is logically equivalent to "high coupling" and "high decoupling" is logically equivalent to low coupling. So in the spirit of simplification, would it not be better to state the distinction as being between "high coupling" people and "low coupling"?
To me, (1) "coupling" suggests specifically joining in pairs much more strongly than "decoupling" suggests specifically detaching pairs and (2) "coupling" suggests that the default state of the things is disconnection, whereas "decoupling" suggests that the default state is connection.
The usual scenario here is that (1) you have lots of things that all relate to one another, and that (2a) most people find it difficult to disentangle, or disapprove of disentangling, and that (2b) all really truly are connected to one another, so that considering them in isolation is a sometimes useful and effective cognitive trick rather than any sort of default.
For all those reasons I think "decoupling" is a better term than "coupling" here. (I also like the opposition decoupling/contextualizing, as found in some of the earlier things Nernst links to, rather than more-decoupling/less-decoupling. When faced with a pile of interrelated things, sometimes you want to decouple them and sometimes you want to pay special attention to the interrelations. It's not as simple as there being some people who are good at decoupling and some who aren't. Though of course most people are bad at decoupling and bad at contextualizing...)
I definitely think Nerst has things the right way round, but I'm having trouble making explcit why. One reason though that I can make explicit is that, well, tangling everything together is the default. Decoupling -- orthogonality, unbundling, separation of concerns, hugging the query -- is rarer, takes work, and is worth pointing out.
This post seems to be making a few claims, which I think can be evaluated separately:
1) Decoupling norms exist
2) Contextualizing norms exist
3) Decoupling and contextualization norms are useful to think as opposites (either as a dichotomy or spectrum)
(i.e. there are enough people using those norms that it's a useful way to carve up the discussion-landscape)
There's a range of "strong" / "weak" versions of these claims – decoupling and/or contextualization might be principled norms that some people explicitly endorse, or they might just be clusters of tendencies people have sometimes.
In the comments of his response post, Zack Davis noted:
It's certainly possible that there's a "general factor" of contextualizing—that people systematically and non-opportunistically vary in how inferentially distant a related claim has to be in order to not create an implicature that needs to be explicitly canceled if false. But I don't think it's obvious, and even if it's true, I don't think it's pedagogically wise to use a politically-motivated appeal-to-consequences as the central case of contextualizing.
And, reading that, I think it may actually the opposite – there is general factor of "decoupling", not contextualizing. By default people are using language for a bunch of reasons all jumbled together, and it's a relatively small set of people who have the deliberately-decouple tendency, skill and/or norm, of "checking individual statements to see if they make sense."
Upon reflection, this is actually more in line with the original Nerst article, which used the terms "Low Decoupling" and "High Decoupling", which less strongly conveys the idea of "contextualizer" being a coherent thing.
On the other hand, Nerst's original post does make some claims about Klein being the sort of person (a journalist) who is "definitively a contextualizer, as opposed to just 'not a decoupler'", here:
While science and engineering disciplines (and analytic philosophy) are populated by people with a knack for decoupling who learn to take this norm for granted, other intellectual disciplines are not. Instead they’re largely composed of what’s opposite the scientist in the gallery of brainy archetypes: the literary or artistic intellectual.
This crowd doesn’t live in a world where decoupling is standard practice. On the contrary, coupling is what makes what they do work. Novelists, poets, artists and other storytellers like journalists, politicians and PR people rely on thick, rich and ambiguous meanings, associations, implications and allusions to evoke feelings, impressions and ideas in their audience. The words “artistic” and “literary” refers to using idea couplings well to subtly and indirectly push the audience’s meaning-buttons.
To a low-decoupler, high-decouplers’ ability to fence off any threatening implications looks like a lack of empathy for those threatened, while to a high-decoupler the low-decouplers insistence that this isn’t possible looks like naked bias and an inability to think straight. This is what Harris means when he says Klein is biased.
Although they're interwoven, I think it might be worth distinguishing some subclaims here (not necessarily made by Nerst or Leong, but I think implied and worth thinking about)
My Epistemic State
Empirical Questions
There's a set of fairly concrete "empirical" questions here, which are basically "if you do a bunch of factor analysis of discussions, would decoupling and/or contextualization and/or any of the specific contextual-subcategories listed above be major predictive power?"
The experiments you'd run for this might be expensive but not very confusing.
I would currently guess:
Conceptual Question
I have a remaining confusion, which is something like "what exactly is a contextualizer?". I feel like I have a crisp definition of "decoupling". I don't have that for contextualizers. Are the three subcategories listed above really 'relatives' or are they just three different groups doing different things? Is it meaningful to put these on a spectrum with decouplers on the other side?
mr-hire suggests:
"How much you and others are willing to think about the consequences of what is said separate from its' truth value."
Which sounds like a plausibly good definition, that maybe applies to all three of the subcategories. But I feel like it's not quite the natural definition for each individual subcategory. (Rather, it's something a bit downstream of each category definition)
"Jumbled" vs "Contextual"
"High decoupling" and "low decoupling" are still pretty confusing terms, even if you get rid of any notion of "low decoupling" being a cogent thing. It occured to me, writing this review, that you might replace the word "contextual" with "jumbled".
Contextual implies some degree of principled norms. Jumbled points more towards "the person is using language for a random mishmash of strategies all thrown together." (Politicians might sometimes be best described as "jumbled", and sometimes as "principled" [but, not necessarily good principles, i.e. 'I will deliberately say whatever causes my party to win']).
...
That's what I got for now.
I really don't like the term jumbled as some people would likely object much more to being labelled as jumbled than as a contextualiser. The rest of this comment makes some good points, but sometimes less is more. I do want to edit this article, but I think I'll mostly engage with Zack's points and reread the article.
The OP comment was optimizing for "improving my understanding of the domain" more than direct advice of how to change the post.
(I'm not necessarily expecting the points and confusions there to resolve within the next month – it's possible that you'll reflect on it a bit and then figure out a slightly different orientation to the post, that distills the various concepts into a new form. Another possible outcome is that you leave the post as-is for now, and then in another year or two after mulling things over someone writers a new post doing a somewhat different thing, that becomes the new referent. Or, it might just turn out that my current epistemic state wasn't that useful. Or other things)
Re: "Jumbled"
I think there's sort of a two-step process that goes into naming things (ironically, or appropriate, which map directly onto the post) – first figuring out "okay what actually is this phenomenon, and what name most accurately describes it?" and then, separately, "okay, what sort of names are going to reliably going to make people angry and distract from the original topic if you apply it to people, and are there alternative names that cleave closely to the truth?"
(my process for generating names in that risk offending is something like a multi-step Babble and Prune, where I generate names aiming to satisfice on "a good explanation of the true phenomenon" and "not likely to be unnecessarily distracting", until I have a name that satisfies both criteria)
I haven't tried generating a maximally good name for Jumbled yet since I wasn't sure this was even carving reality the right way.
But, like, it's not an accident that 'jumbled' is more likely to offend people than 'contextualized'. I do, in fact, think worse of people who have jumbled communication than deliberately contextualized communication. (compare "Virtue Signalling", which is an important term but is basically an insult except among people who have some kind of principled understanding that "Yup, it turns out some of the things I do had unflattering motives and I've come to endorse that, or endorse my current [low] degree of prioritizing changing it.")
I am a conversation consequentialist and think it's best to find ways of politely pointing out unflattering things about people in ways that don't make them defensive. But, it might be that the correct carving of reality includes some unflattering descriptions of people and maybe the best you can do is minimize distraction-damage.
Reply: "Relevance Norms; Or, Gricean Implicature Queers the Decoupling/Contextualizing Binary" (further counterreplies in the comment section)
I argue that this post should not be included in the Best-of-2018 compilation.
Curated for succinctly creating some useful handles for two concepts that have implicitly been coming up a lot. i think this has already been helpful to me when thinking about some confusing/challenging conversations.
Two years later, the concept of decoupled vs contextualizing has remained an important piece of my vocabulary.
I'm glad both for this distillation of Nerst's work (removing some of the original political context that might make it more distracting to link to in the middle of an argument), and in particular for the jargon-optimization that followed ("contextualized" is much more intuitive than "low-decoupling.")
This post has been object-level useful, for navigating particular disagreements. (I think in those cases I haven't brought it up directly myself, but I've benefited from a sometimes-heated-discussion having access to the concepts).
I think it's also been useful at a more meta-level, as one of the concepts in my toolkit that enable me to think higher level thoughts in the domain of group norms and frame disagreements. A recent facebook discussion was delving into a complicated set of differences in norms/expectations, where decoupled/contextualizing seemed to be one of the ingredients but not the entirety. Having the handy shorthand and common referent allowed it to only take up a single working-memory slot while still being able to think about the other complexities at play.
This post has been object-level useful, for navigating particular disagreements.
Can you give specific examples? I've basically only seen "contextualizing norms" used as a stonewalling tactic, but you've probably seen discussions I haven't.
The most recent example was this facebook thread. I'm hoping over the next week to find some other concrete examples to add to the list, although I think the most of the use cases here were in hard-to-find-after-the-fact-facebook-threads.
Note that much of the value add here is being able to succinctly talk about the problem, sometimes saying "hey, this is a high-decoupling conversation/space, read this blogpost if you don't know what that means".
I don't think I've run into people citing "contextualizing norms" as a reason not to talk about things, although I've definitely run into people operating under contextualizing norms in stonewally-ways without having a particular name for it. I'd expect that to change as the jargon becomes more common though, and if you have examples of that happening already that'd be good to know.
(Hmm – Okay I guess it'd make sense if you saw some of our past debates as something like me directly advocating for contextualizing, in a way that seemed harmful to you. I hadn't been thinking there through the decoupled/contextualized lens, not quite sure if the lens fits, but might make sense upon reflection)
It still seems like having the language here is a clear net benefit though.
as the jargon becomes more common
If the jargon becomes more common. (The Review Phase hasn't even started yet!) I wrote a reply explaining in more detail why I don't like this post.
I think this article is a considerable step forward, but it could benefit from some examples. I think I have a pretty good idea what this is about (and share the horror of being called out by a low-decoupler for being some kind of ism), but still.
Hmm, well the article has an example, but it is super long and I'm trying to avoid this becoming political. Any suggestions for examples?
The example you use is already CW-enough that high-decouplers may be suspicious or hostile of the point you are trying to make.
Then again, maybe anything elsewould be too far removed from our shared experience that it wouldn't serve as a quick and powerful illustration of your point.
Here are some suggestions made with both of these points in mind:
--The original example Scott uses about a Jew in future Czarist Russia constantly hearing about how powerful Jews are and how evil Israel is.
--Flipping the script a bit, how about an example in which someone goes around saying "86% of rationalists are straight white men" (or something like that, I don't know the actual number).
--Or: "Effective Altruists are usually people who are biased towards trying to solve their problems using math."
Come to think of it, I think including one of those flip-script examples would be helpful in other ways as well.
At the same time, I don't want to fall for the Fallacy of the Undistributed Middle and assume that both perspectives are equally valid.
Minor possible quibble: based on the definition in the link given, I think Fallacy of the Undistributed Middle doesn't refer to assuming a the deep wisdom position that two sides of a debate each have merit.
The fallacy of the undistributed middle (Lat. non distributio medii) is a formal fallacy that is committed when the middle term in a categorical syllogism is not distributed in either the minor premise or the major premise. It is thus a syllogistic fallacy.)
This is one of the Major splits I see in norms on LW (the other being combat vs. Nurture). Having a handy tag for this is quite useful for pointing at a thing without having to grasp to explain it.
My nomination seconds the things that were said in the first paragraphs of Raemon's nomination.
Agreed with quanticle, but otherwise think this is a very helpful dichotomy to have a handle for.
Isn't it just the distinction between how facts are used in scientific discourse (you state a fact, expect it to be confirmed or challenged) vs. how they are used in political discourse (carefully select other fact to augment it and suit your political narrative)? I guess Umberto Eco would have had something to say about that.
I can see the models usefulness but I think you are impling they are equal. This seems wrong. Decoupling required more specific knowledge and concentration and is more analogous to Kahneman's slow thinking. Obvious context can be thought of in a rich way but only after the individual ideas have been richly defined (often in previous thoughts). We cycle between the two approaches but I feel decoupling required the greater focus and is lacking when we discuss topics we are unfamiliar with (and a possible link with the Dunning Kruger effect). My understanding of cognitive load theory from education (limited working memory) also seems relavent. By limiting context we can more intensely analyse each aspect, repackage them efficiently and accurately before returning contextual information the whole problem. This seems to me the classic method of enlightenment thinking. Obviously understanding why other people might misunderstand d this is important however that is an argument around politics, rhetoric and persuasion not about clarity of thought.
Finally pure contextualisation is only about outcomes and decoupling only about process. Without understanding alternate approaches (which requires specialist knowledge) our assessment of the best method to achieve our outcome is likely flawed.
John Nerst: "To a contextualizer, decouplers’ ability to fence off any threatening implications looks like a lack of empathy for those threatened, while to a decoupler, the contextualizer's insistence that this isn’t possible looks like naked bias and an inability to think straight"[1]. |
A particularly thorny—yet very common—way for a discussion to break down is when participants strongly disagree about the correct scope of a discussion. If neither side is willing to compromise, progress often becomes impossible.
John Nerst identifies a difference in expectations that is particularly prone to causing such issues:
What these norms entail:[2] | |
---|---|
Decoupling norms | People have a right to expect the truth of their claims to be considered on their own merits, with no obligation to pay heed to worries about the "broader context" or the "implications" of such speech. Insisting on raising these issues, despite a firm request to consider an idea in isolation, is likely a sign of careless reasoning or an attempt at deflection. |
Contextualizing norms | Being a responsible actor necessarily involves considering certain contextual factors and implications when deciding what kinds of statements are acceptable. Not taking these factors into account most likely reflects limited awareness, a lack of care, or even deliberate evasion — especially if the speaker ignores an explicit request. |
Suppose data showed that people born in even-numbered years committed murders at twice the rate of the general population. Can you state this directly and, if so, must you issue a disclaimer?
A decoupler would tend to see it as unreasonable to object to a direct statement of facts. Here's an example of how someone with this viewpoint might think:
Surely, as a citizen in a free society, I should just be able to state the truth directly? After all, we're adults. Additionally, we shouldn't have to issue disclaimers all the time. This kind of compelled speech makes it hard to speak frankly. They amount to soft censorship in the short term and risk creating a slippery slope toward harsher censorship in the long term. Furthermore, it impedes the scientific and intellectual progress that has raised both living conditions and moral standards.
However, contextualizers tend to see the situation quite differently. Here's one possible expression of this:[3]
It would be deeply irresponsible to make statements that risk creating a stigma around even-numbered folk. Besides, is there any point in doing so? After all, you can't just assume that people born in an even year are criminal by default! At the very least, you should issue a disclaimer to prevent bad actors from using your words to push bad faith narratives. It's not as if that’s difficult! I'm not demanding that you say anything untrue, just that you exercise prudence with what you say regarding a few particularly charged issues.
For both norms, it's easy to think of situations where insisting on them seems dogmatic. Scott Alexander's excellent post, 📖 Weak men are superweapons
, lays out how true statements can be weaponized to destroy a group's credibility. If you have good reason to believe that someone is using this strategy against you, with the intent to cause serious harm, it would be shockingly naive to let them force you into strict adherence to decoupling norms.
On the other hand, it's a very common strategy[4] to frame every disliked action as part of someone's agenda (neoliberal, cultural Marxist, far-right—take your pick).
Agendas are real, but wielding "universal counter-arguments" is one of the easiest ways to "mindkill" yourself, so I strongly encourage you to be wary here.
Contextualizers are correct that it would be rather naive to make certain true statements in a situation that is sufficiently highly charged. But what counts as sufficiently charged and what limitations are reasonable in such a case?
Unfortunately, there isn't a simple answer here. It would be nice if there were, but I suspect that making the right choice ultimately requires wisdom.
Even if it is best for some conversations not to be maximally public, it still seems important for society's epistemics to preserve at least some spaces for decoupling-style conversations.[5] Such spaces create sites of resistance against cultural limitations arbitrarily imposed for political advantage, rather than genuinely serving the common good.
❦ |
🎁 Extras
|
Executive summary[6]: In short, both decoupling and contextualizing norms have merit, but each also has flaws. Navigating this tension doesn’t come down to rules alone, but requires wisdom. That said, it's important to preserve at least some spaces for decoupled truth-seeking conversations to maintain a society's long-term epistemic health. |
❦ |
Key points: • Decoupling norms: Ideas should be evaluated purely on their merits, without requiring disclaimers or concern for the broader implications of having the discussion—objections to this may be interpreted as political bias or deflection. • Contextualizing norms: Responsible communication requires considering the possible social or political consequences of the speech act, and ignoring them could be considered naive, careless, or evasive. • Illustrative example: The claim that “people born in even-numbered years commit more murders” highlights the clash—decouplers defend the right to state facts directly, while contextualizers worry about stigma and how malicious actors might weaponize such statements. • Cautions against dogmatism: Both approaches can be weaponized—strict decoupling can, in the worst case, mean standing aside while people coordinate towards genocide, while overzealous contextualizing can be used to derail discussions by invoking claims of hidden agendas. • Author’s stance: Context matters in highly charged situations, but the judgment of what counts as "excessively charged" ultimately requires wisdom rather than fixed rules. • Importance of decoupling spaces: Even if some discussions should be constrained, preserving decoupled forums is vital for epistemic health and as a safeguard against politically motivated suppression. |
A Deep Dive into the Harris-Klein Controversy - John Nerst's original (and excellent!) post |
❦ |
Putanumonit - Explores the relationship between decoupling and mistake/conflict theory |
❦ |
Relevance Norms; Or, Gricean Implicature Queers the Decoupling/Contextualizing Binary - Argues that the real distinction isn't how much people contextualize, but what they consider to be "relevant context". "The concept of "contextualizing norms" has the potential to legitimize derailing discussions for arbitrary political reasons by eliding the key question of which contextual concerns are genuinely relevant, thereby conflating legitimate and illegitimate bids for contextualization. Real discussions adhere to what we might call "relevance norms": it is almost universally "eminently reasonable to expect certain contextual factors or implications to be addressed." Disputes arise over which certain contextual factors those are, not whether context matters at all." |
Hat tip to prontab for sharing this article. He actually uses low decoupling/high decoupling, but I prefer avoiding double negatives. Both John Nerst and prontab passed up the opportunity to post on this topic here, so I decided to pick up the baton. |
This quote is slightly edited. It also serves as a TL;DR.
Honestly, this is more of a spectrum than a binary. However, it is easier to explain as a binary.
I'm sure many people will want to point out that this does not really represent the average view held by contextualizers. Sure, this only represents a more sympathetic contextualizer, but I think that's perfectly fine as it makes sense to engage with the most defensible version of a viewpoint.
"Strategy" — I don't mean to imply that it's always, or even typically, consciously chosen.
Eliezer's Local Validity as a Key to Sanity and Civilisation articulates the importance of such conversations well.
This recap is a hand-edited version of the SummaryBot output.