Suppose I have a deck of four cards:  The ace of spades, the ace of hearts, and two others (say, 2C and 2D).

You draw two cards at random.

Scenario 1:  I ask you "Do you have the ace of spades?"  You say "Yes."  Then the probability that you are holding both aces is 1/3:  There are three equiprobable arrangements of cards you could be holding that contain AS, and one of these is AS+AH.

Scenario 2:  I ask you "Do you have an ace?"  You respond "Yes."  The probability you hold both aces is 1/5:  There are five arrangements of cards you could be holding (all except 2C+2D) and only one of those arrangements is AS+AH.

Now suppose I ask you "Do you have an ace?"

You say "Yes."

I then say to you:  "Choose one of the aces you're holding at random (so if you have only one, pick that one).  Is it the ace of spades?"

You reply "Yes."

What is the probability that you hold two aces?

Argument 1:  I now know that you are holding at least one ace and that one of the aces you hold is the ace of spades, which is just the same state of knowledge that I obtained in Scenario 1.  Therefore the answer must be 1/3.

Argument 2:  In Scenario 2, I know that I can hypothetically ask you to choose an ace you hold, and you must hypothetically answer that you chose either the ace of spades or the ace of hearts.  My posterior probability that you hold two aces should be the same either way.  The expectation of my future probability must equal my current probability:  If I expect to change my mind later, I should just give in and change my mind now.  Therefore the answer must be 1/5.

Naturally I know which argument is correct.  Do you?

New Comment
92 comments, sorted by Click to highlight new comments since:
Some comments are truncated due to high volume. (⌘F to expand all)Change truncation settings

Argument 2 is correct. When the person replies "Yes," after choosing randomly, you learn not only that he has the ace of spades, but also that on one trial, he selected it after choosing randomly from his aces. This makes the combinations "AS, 2C" and "AS, 2D" more probable than "AS, AH", since the first two combinations give a 100% chance of a positive response, while the third gives only a 50% chance of a positive response. So each of the first two combinations is twice as likely as the third, so the probability of the third combination, namely two aces, goes to 1/5.

7cousin_it
I reached the same solution. This looks like a riff on the Monty Hall problem, whose solution also hinges on the fact that the host opens a door randomly or non-randomly depending on your initial choice.
0MatthewB
This is exactly what I thought when I read the problem.
1[anonymous]
This.

Answering without looking at other comments, will check those after:

The assumption in the first argument is wrong, you in fact have different information than the info you have in scenario 1. In scenario 1, the information you have is "I answer yes when asked if I have a spade"

In this situation you have the information that I have an ace and if I pick one of the aces at random to reveal to you, I reveal that I have a spade.

The relevant likelihoods are DIFFERENT:

P("I have at least one ace, and if I choose one at random (or just the one if I have only one), to reveal to you, I reveal to you I have a spade" | I have both aces) = 1/2

P("You asked me if I have a spade? Well, yes, I do have a spade" | I have both aces) = 1

(modulo standard disclaimers on assigning P = 1 to any state of affairs, of course)

Argument 2 is correct. What changes is the probability that I hold just an ace of spades or just an ace of hearts.

0Furcas
Yup. In other words, the remaining possibilities are the same in both scenarios (AS/AH, AS/2C, AS/2D), but the probabilities attached to these possibilities are different. In scenario 2 the observation that one of the cards is the ace of spades does more than rule out possibilities, it also shifts the probability mass from the AS/AH possibility toward the AS/2C and AS/2D possibilities, in such a way that the probability attached to the AS/AH possibility goes 'back' to what it was when there were five possibilities. It shows that drawing little boxes corresponding to each possibility and carefully crossing out those that were contradicted by the evidence is only a poor approximation of Bayes' theorem.
0Psy-Kosh
Well, drawing boxes and crossing out would work here if you explicitly have boxes for "how does the card holder answer the questions" or in this case "how does the card holder answer the "if you have aces, pick one at random, is it a spade"? It just takes a bit more detail.
0AdeleneDawner
I made a diagram already. Note that we were using 'prefer' to refer to the ace you pick when you pick between the two if you have both.
0Peter_de_Blanc
Ditto. Psy-Kosh has correctly observed that argument 2 is correct, and has correctly pointed out the flaw in argument 1.
[-]Emile120

Argument 2.

The second question of the last scenario is exactly equivalent to "show me the ace you've chosen", which gives zero new information about whether you have two aces or not.

1Richard_Kennaway
This is the clearest answer I've seen.
0SarahSrinivasan
But Argument 1 has an intuition pump based on equivalent states of knowledge, too, and it's wrong! ;) This equivalence works but does not generalize well, as it would fail on a three As two 2s variant.
0[anonymous]
The states of knowledge in scenarios 1 and 2 aren't equivalent. It's true that the same possibilities are ruled out in scenario 2 that are ruled out in scenario 1 (and therefore, the same possibilities remain in both scenarios), but in scenario 2 the observation that one of the cards is the ace of spades does more than rule out possibilities, it also shifts the probability mass from the AS/AH possibility toward the AS/2C and AS/2D possibilities, in such a way that the probability attached to the AS/AH possibility doesn't change. Put more succinctly, the remaining possibilities are the same in both scenarios, but the probabilities attached to these possibilities are different, so it's not true that the states of knowledge are the same.

Here's code to compute the probability empirically (I got an answer of 0.2051384 for 10000 draws. It's written in C# but can be readily converted to other functional languages such as Haskell).

var cards = new[] { "AH", "AS", "2C", "2D" };  
var pairs = cards.Combinations (2);  
var pairsWithAce = pairs.Where (p => p.Any (c => c.Contains ("A")));  

var drawsWithAce =  
(  
    from i in Enumerable.Range (1, 10000)  
    let randomPairWithAce = pairsWithAce.ElementAt (rand.Next (pairsWithAce.Count()))
... (read more)

You have three sets of 100 cards - either all aces, no aces, or exactly one ace; all three are equally likely. You lay the cards out in front of you.

I either (a) ask you whether you've got an ace, and you say yes, or (b) turn over one card chosen at random, and find that it's an ace.

In both cases I now know that you've got at least one ace, but the posterior probability that you have all aces is 1/2 in case "a" , and (I think) 100/101 in case "b".

Argument 2 isn't expressed clearly enough for me to understand it; it seems to be missing some steps. But the answer is 1/5.

Argument 2 is correct. There are lots of ways to show this, since it has a numeric conclusion, and there are lots of correct ways to arrive at that number.

Where precisely does Argument 1 fail?

Argument 1 says "which is just the same state of knowledge..." but it is flat-out lying. One direction is fine: if you answer "yes, yes" to Scenario 3, then you would answer "yes" in Scenario 1. But if you would answer "yes" to Scenario 1, then you would not answer "yes, yes" to Scenario 3. This is not the same state o... (read more)

The question I think is interesting is: When you throw away probability information and keep only possibility information, like when you go from "a random ace was a spade" in Scenario 2 to "there was an ace which was a spade" in Scenario 1, when does that cause bias? How do you have to think about the information you have left? When can you just condition on your information being true, and when do you have to think about the probability that you would have been left with this information and not some other information?

The probability is 1/5 (as independently calculated by me). I've no idea if argument 2 is correct, because I don't understand it. My reasoning:

There are 6 combinations of 2 cards: AsAh, As2c, As2d, Ah2c, Ah2d, 2c2d.

Of these, only the first 3 (AsAh, As2c, As2d) could I have answered yes to both questions (assuming I'm not lying, wihch is outside the context).

But if I have AsAh, only 1/2 the time would I have answered yes to the second question. So AsAh needs 1/2 the weight of the other 2 possibilities.

So the probability is (1/2)/(2+1/2) = 1/5.

I'm sorry to confess that I fell for the equivalent of Argument 1 in a similar puzzle in the past.

In terms of the current puzzle, I realized my mistake only when I realized that my state of knowledge isn't just that you're holding the Ace of Spades. I also know that you told me that you're holding the Ace of Spades, instead of some other card that you might have told me about. This knowledge introduces a new conditional probability into the Bayesian computation, which then yields the correct answer.

Argument 2. Bayes' Law doesn't lie.

I'm wondering about your reasons for posting a straightforward probability question (as a top-level post rather than an Open Thread comment, no less). Are you trying to take a reading of how competent the average LW contributor currently is on trivial questions? Are you setting up a real-world problem analogous to this, where most people get the wrong answer? Or is it something else entirely?

If the problem is too easy, consider the meta-problem: what makes argument 1 seductive, and how can we teach ourselves to easily see through such arguments in the future?

(In this case it was easy to see the flaw in argument 1 because argument 2 was laid out right beside it. What if all we had was argument 1?)

I think perhaps our intuitive understanding of "state of knowledge" is wrong, and we need to fix it, but I'm not sure how.

0Morendil
In this particular case, all we need to do is encode our "state of knowledge" formally into the relevant probabilities, mooting all appeals to intuition. However this is a "toy problem", in real-world situations I expect that it will not be practical to enumerate all possible outcomes. I am helping a colleague of mine investigate application of Bayesian inference methods to the question of software testing, and we're seeing much the same difficulty: on an extremely simplified problem we can draw definite conclusions, but we don't yet know how to extend those conclusions to situations the industry would consider relevant.
5Eliezer Yudkowsky
I occasionally get requests for more homework problems. You're also correct that I was curious about the average skill level on LW. In retrospect, though, what I should have done was start a Bayesian Fun Problems Thread. Will try to remember to do that next time I have a puzzle.

Argument 2, I figure. Finding out if a randomly chosen ace is a AS or not tells you nothing about p(2A) - since the chance of choosing AS is 50-50 for both 2A and across all 4 of the !2A cases.

That's assuming a genuine random choice. If there's a bias that causes the choice to become non-random once hearing the AS question, that might mess things up.

I have to agree that both arguments seem to be lacking, and the correct method for finding the answer is one of (enumerate the possibilities | do some math).

ETA: I should stop using regex-style disjunctions given the syntax for "given" used extensively here for probability.

[-]Cyan20

I didn't read either argument before cranking up Bayes' Theorem. After the first question, the five remaining possibilities are equiprobable, so the posterior probabilities are proportional to the likelihoods of each possibility. The two non-pairs containing the ace of spades have likelihood 1 and the pair of aces has likelihood 0.5. Normalizing the likelihoods gives 1/5 chances for the pair of aces.

[-]N_R20

I think Scenario 2 is wrong.

If you know, that one card is an ace, the probability that the second card is also an ace is 1/3, because there are two non aces and one ace remaining.

The tricky thing is, that it´s completely irrelevant, if the ace is of spades or of hearts. Remember, the question is if you hold both aces! Just distinguish between aces and non-aces..

3Bo102010
It helps to enumerate the possible worlds: In the beginning you can have: (1) AS, AH (2) AS, 2C (3) AS, 2D (4) AH, 2C (5) AH, 2D (6) 2C, 2D After answering "Yes" to "Do you have an ace," the possible worlds are (1) AS, AH (2) AS, 2C (3) AS, 2D (4) AH, 2C (5) AH, 2D That is, in world (6) you would not answer "Yes," so it is eliminated. After picking one of your aces randomly, the possible worlds are: (1a) AS, AH -> AS in one possible sub-world (1b) AS, AH -> AH in another possible sub-world (2) AS, 2C -> AS (3) AS, 2D -> AS (4) AH, 2C -> AH (5) AH, 2D -> AH You're counting (1a) and (1b) as 1 each, then dividing by the six worlds to get 1/3, but the trick is that those two worlds are not as likely as the others - (edited for clarity) half the time world (1) evolves into (1a); half the time it evolves into (1b). So if you count (1a) and (1b) as 0.5 each and the rest as 1 each, then the probability of having both aces is (0.5 + 0.5) / (0.5 + 0.5 + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1) = 1/5.
0whpearson
I don't get what your saying... see my probability tree diagram and tell me why you are weighting them differently?
3Bo102010
I don't understand what your tree is trying to show. However, I think my explanation above shows why world's (1a) and (1b) are weighted less than (2) through (5) - they both come from parent world (1). If you gave (1a) and (1b) weight=1, you would be giving parent world 1 weight=2.

Argument 2 is correct. Showing an ace provides no relevant information. If you want to do the math, I like Blueberry's solution. Or: if you have 2 aces, then your chances of saying "yes, it's AS" are 50-50 since you were equally likely to have chosen either ace (you picked one at random), and if you have 1 ace, then your chances of saying "yes, it's AS" are 50-50 since you are equally likely to have either ace, so your "yes" answer does not provide any information about how many aces you have.

Argument 1 is wrong because in ... (read more)

Before drawing the cards, I decided randomly whether to "prefer" hearts or spades, so that if I had both cards I would tell you about the preferred one. That gives me twelve scenarios, of which five result in the answers that I gave you, of which I hold both aces in only one. Therefore 1/5.

If your second question was instead "Are you holding the Ace of Spades?" as in Scenario 1, then I'm twice as likely to answer "Yes" in the instance that I really have both aces as I was before - ie there are now six scenarios allowed by m... (read more)

Argument 2 is correct, but I'm having considerably difficulty putting the reason into succinct terms in a way that'd feel satisfying for me, even after reading all the comments here.

However, here's the thoroughly worked out answer for anyone who wants it:

We start with no questions asked. All of the six possible sets are equiprobable.

  • (AS 2C): 1/6
  • (AS 2D): 1/6
  • (AS AH): 1/6
  • (AH 2C): 1/6
  • (AH 2D): 1/6
  • (2C 2D): 1/6

Next you ask the first question, "do you have an ace?" I respond "yes". This eliminates the (2C 2D) possibility. This leaves ... (read more)

0whpearson
I disagree with this step (my rot13d explanation hasn't garnered much attention). I don't think the sets are equiprobable. Consider the following tree The first question represents asking what the first ace drawn was, the second question what the other card was. As the first question is 50:50 either way and the second each card has a equal probability. However as AHAS comes up twice on the tree it has twice the weighting and 1/3 probability from the start. Or to think of it another way. You know they have one ace, what are the options for the other card. They are equally probably 2C, 2D and the other Ace. So I say it is 1/3 the chance of getting two aces, once you know they have one ace.
0Kaj_Sotala
I believe AdeleneDawner is right: yes, there are three options each in the last branch, but they aren't all equally likely. Though I'm uncertain of how to show it from the top off my head: give me a while.
0AdeleneDawner
I'm almost done putting a diagram together, if you want it.
0Kaj_Sotala
Please do show it.
5AdeleneDawner
The colors of the squares in the grids show how you'd answer the question 'Is your preferred ace the ace of spades?' and whether you have 1 or 2 aces. The 'P=' notation in the corner of each grid shows what you're preferring; in the first case you always prefer the first ace drawn; the latter two are meant to be read together and assume that you're picking which ace you prefer ahead of time with a coin toss. The red and green squares to the side show how many of each response you could see in each case.
1whpearson
Thanks that cleared it up for me. I've been trying analyse where I went wrong. I reformulated the question in a way that I didn't notice lost information
0AdeleneDawner
Also, simply asking "Do you have the ace of spades?' returns a chart that looks like the P=AS one; red (and peach, if 'Do you have an ace?' isn't asked first) squares are instances where you answer 'No', and the remaining 4 light green and 2 dark green squares show the 1 in 3 chance that you have 2 aces given that you answered 'Yes'.
0AdeleneDawner
What about the instances where you get 2C or 2D first, and then one of the aces?
0whpearson
My first question is phrased as "first ace drawn", the second question is "other card drawn". This card could have been drawn before or after, it doesn't matter which (unless it is the other ace in which case it couldn't have been drawn before). Picking the first ace is really just a way to fix what one definite unknown ace is in some way, so you can ask what the other cards are.
0[anonymous]
The flaw in this argument is that you don't have an equal probability of drawing a 2 as an ace alongside your first ace, since there are two possibilities for drawing the twos--drawing them before or after--but only one for drawing the second ace, since it must be drawn after.
0AdeleneDawner
Missed that on my first read-through, but it still kind of points in the direction of the problem with your chart. Assume that the first ace is AS. There's two instances where the other card could be 2C (AS then 2C, or 2C then AS), two instances where it could be 2D (AS then 2D, or 2D then AS), and one instance where it could be AH (AS then AC, but not AC then AS). The three branches for 'other card' are not equally likely.
0whpearson
Okay I'll dispense with draw order entirely. Imagine if instead of asking them if they had an ace, ask them if they had an ace and mentally select one of their aces to be the primary ace at random. They don't tell you what it is or give any other information. So the first question on my tree is what is their primary ace, and the second question is what is their other card. Their primary ace still has a 50:50 chance of being either (if they only have one ace, it could have been either drawn from the deck, and if they have two then it is selected randomly by the person with the cards). If you guess that their primary ace is one of the aces then the other cards are drawn from a pool of three possibilities. Does this clear what I am getting at up for you?
1AdeleneDawner
I see what you're doing, but I still think you're making a mistake: Just because there are three possibilities, doesn't mean that those possibilities are equally likely. It's similar to flipping a fair coin twice; you could get two heads, two tails, or one of each. There are three possible outcomes, but the 'one of each' option is twice as likely as either of the other two.
0Bo102010
That's how I did it too, thanks for saving my the typing.

I'm not so great at this kind of thing but a quick simulation script says: Argument 2 is correct (or at least the answer is 1/5).

4Liron
I recently ran a quick simulation to estimate the answer to 7 x 5. In case anyone is wondering: it's 35.000.
4kpreid
I think the point here is “Why simulate when you can get an exact answer?” In which case, the consideration is whether it is easier to ‘see’ that the simulation program is correct or that the reasoning for the exact answer is correct. A similar situation that comes to mind is “exact” symbolic integration vs. “approximate” numerical integration; symbolic integration is not always possible (in terms of “simple” operations) whereas numeric integration is straightforward to perform, no matter how complex the original formula, but inexact. ∫(0 to 7) 5 dx ≈ 35.000
1ShardPhoenix
Yes - while reasoning through the problem might give you a deeper understanding, if you just want to know the answer it can sometimes be easier to be sure that your program is correct than that your mathematical reasoning is correct.
2Alicorn
I'm curious: how do you estimate the product of seven and five?
3Liron
I ran a bunch of trials where I randomly chose floating point values A and B from the interval [1, 1000]. Then I either added A to itself B times or added B to itself A times. Then I took an average of all the sums, weighting each by the "relevance factor" (5/A)(7/B).
1thomblake
I know this was trying to be funny, but that algorithm didn't really use simulation to estimate 7 x 5. It just calculates 7 x 5 a bunch of times and takes the average, with the added step of multiplying and dividing by AB. But then, I'm maybe not creative enough to come up with an algorithm that would actually output an approximation of 7 x 5 using some probabilistic method that doesn't include calculating 7 x 5.
7Nick_Tarleton
Throw darts at a unit square, take the fraction that hit a point (x < .7, y < .5) and multiply by 100. (Also works to calculate pi.)
4Zack_M_Davis
I get 36.0.
0[anonymous]
It's samping variation. Set trials = 1e9 and see what you get.
2Liron
If I knew how to take fractions, I would have just done 7/(1/5).
1Liron
Yeah, I guess I should have made the effort to understand the principles of the subject I was reading about rather than do a random trivial programming exercise with no general applicability whose dominance by simple mathematics I could have predicted a priori.
0[anonymous]
I ran a bunch of trials where I randomly chosen floating point values A and B from the interval [0, 1000]. Then I either added A to itself B times or added B to itself A times. Then I took an average of all the sums, weighting each by the "relevance constant" (5/A)(7/B).

Heh! After the first 4 answers, there is an even split!

This is the way that I see the problem (please correct me if I'm wrong).

ANSWER: 1/5

We know that the person has an Ace of spades in their hand which means the following are the only combinations the person could have is AH and AS, 2C and AS, 2D and AS. The probability of the person answering the question with "I have an Ace of spades" when the person has the combination of AH and AS is 1/2. The probability with 2C and AS is 1 and the probability of 2D and AS is 1 as there is only one ace in these combinations meaning the person would be forc... (read more)

The first reply eliminates the no-ace case from six equally likely cases, leaving two aces as one of five equally likely cases. So the probability is one fifth. (The second question is irrelevant, by symmetry.)

-1dellbarnes
If we have an ace in the hand, 2 of those "equally likely cases" are no longer possible. (2 of those cases involve the other ace and a non-ace card.)

Follow-up puzzle: what if the second question would, instead of asking to pick an ace at random, have asked "is at least one of the cards you're holding the Ace of Spades?" After establishing that you have at least one ace, that is. One could make the same two arguments as for the original question.

0Jack
Maybe I misread but this looks just like scenario 1 to me.
[-]Jack10

Argument 2 is right. Here is how I think about it. If I am holding one ace the probability it is a spade is 1/2 (there are only two aces). If I am holding two aces the probability that one selected randomly is the spade is also 1/2. The cases aren't distinguished by the expected response to the question "Do you hold the ace of spades?" so that information cannot possibly be used to update the prior answer of 1/5.

There's an easy way to figure out the probability: say that the person holding the cards flips a coin. If he has two Aces, when asked to pick one, heads means he picks the Ace of Spades, and tails means he picks the Ace of Hearts.

There are twelve possible outcomes: 6 possible two-card hands times 2 possibilities for the coin flip. The person's responses have ruled out all but five: 1) heads, AS, AH; 2) heads, AS, 2C; 3) tails, AS, 2C; 4) heads, AS, 2D; 5) tails, AS, 2D. Each is equally likely and he has two Aces in 1), so the probability must be 1/5.

(We don't have the same information as in Scenario 1 because the coin flip made it less likely that he has two Aces, as Unknowns explained.)

The conclusion of the second is correct, but to arrive at that conclusion I had to write out all the possibilities and observe how the sequence of answers pruned them. I only understood the second argument when I realised that the symmetry of spades and hearts is what makes it work.

By that symmetry, the posterior probability of having two aces after answering yes to the final question about the ace of spades -- P(2A|AS=yes) for short -- must equal P(2A|AH=yes). But P(2A|AH=yes) = P(2A|AS=no). So the posterior after asking about the ace of spades is indepe... (read more)

I see another way to show that 1/5 is the correct solution:

P(2 Aces | Ace of Spades revealed)= P(2 Aces AND Ace of Spades revealed)/P(Ace of Spades revealed)

(note: for further calculations, I'm assuming that there are 5 possible hands and the probability for each hand is 1/5, since it already has been revealed that there is at least one Ace. The end result would be the same if you would also set aside a random card in case you have no Ace,but the probabilities in the steps before the end results would have to change accordingly)


P(2 Aces AND Ace of Spades reveled)=P(2 Aces)*1/2 = 1/5 * 1/2 =1/10

P(Ace of Spades revealed)= 2/5 * 1 + 1/5 * 1/2 = 5/10

(1/10)/(5/10)=1/5

Even further: the probability that I can guess your hand is 1/5. However, the probability that you have 2 aces is 1/3. No?

Further: write out your 12 possible trial pulls. Raw odds of ace-ace =2/12. Once an ace is pulled, do two things: cross out the two null-null pulls. The odds of ace-ace appear to be 2/10, but... We didn't draw out Schrodinger's ace; it is either ah or as. pick one (it doesnt matter which, they are symmetrical in distribution) and cross out the combinations that do not have this ace. As the waveform collapses the true odds of ace-ace appear- 2/6. Do you see that? We didnt draw an equally hearty or spadey ace, it had to be one of them or the other, which mad... (read more)

Sorry to zombie this thread, but I could use some help.

Hmm.. I'm going with 1/3 for 2 reasons. i might be wrong, but maybe I can explain how I am wrong well enough for someone to help me see it, because I'm stumped here.

reason one, from the bottom end: when the answers are yes-yes, there are only 3 possible types hands, ace-ace, and (2) ace-null, each as likely. Weighting probabilities based on how one may answer "yes-no" and still have ace-ace seems erroneous when the answers are yes-yes.

reason two, from the top end: It seems that a false set is... (read more)

1Jasmine Bacon
Hi, This is why I'm pretty sure its 1/5 (although I don't understand Eliezer's reasoning in Argument 2, this is my reasoning - which by all means could be the same, I'm just not very good at dissecting flowery language). If you ignore the fact that the person has the ability to choose the Ace of Hearts (if they have both aces) in the second question, yes it would be 1/3, however if the person does have both spades and they choose to say spade instead of hearts then that changes the probability as it means that there's less of a chance the person chose spades over hearts rather than just being forced in the other two scenarios to be forced to choose spades. We know that the person has an Ace of spades in their hand which means the following are the only combinations the person could have is AH and AS, 2C and AS, 2D and AS. The probability of the person answering the question with "I have an Ace of spades" when the person has the combination of AH and AS is 1/2. The probability with 2C and AS is 1 and the probability of 2D and AS is 1 as there is only one ace in these combinations meaning the person would be forced to choose these. There for the probability is (1/2)/(1/2+1+1) which simplifies to 1/5. Mathematically this can be shown as: AH AS P(choose AS)=1/2 P(choose AH)=1/2 2C AS P(choose AS)=1 2D AS P(choose AS)=1 therefore P(both) = (1/2)/(1/2+1+1) = 1/5
[-][anonymous]00

I find the responses funny and interesting. Should I write a post explaining this problem, since I don't think it's possible to achieve decent signal to noise by writing another comment? Naturally, I know where the error is.

Combination vs. permutation, right? I don't care which ace is where; I just care if, among the three cards that the other card COULD be, that card is the one ace left.

But how about this: I deal each of us two cards out of a deck of AS, AH, 2C, and 2D. I ask you if you have an ace and you say yes. Surely the odds of me having both 2C and 2D are the same as above.

I figured this before reading your arguments:

If you have two aces, the probability that the one you pick is the ace of spades is 0.5. If you have only one ace, the probability that it's the ace of spades is also 0.5 (and if so the probability that you pick it is 1).

The conditional probabilities are 50/50 in both cases. Therefore the evidence has no influence on the prior probability. The probability of two aces remains 1/5.

As for the arguments:

I think argument 1 is oversimplifying. We'd have the same information as in scenario 1 if we'd just ask "... (read more)

The key to this is to understand that in half of all cases where two aces were drawn, the second random step will pick the heart 1/2 the time.

Thus - the first step selects 5 out of 6 possible outcomes. In the second step, 4 of the 5 cases have fixed outcomes; the other (Aa) has two posssible outcomes.

Thus there are six possible final states:

1 a D showing a (1/5) 2 a d showing a (1/5) 3 A D showing A (1/5) 4 A d showing A (1/5) 6 A a showing a (1/10) 6 A a showing A (1/10)

The answer to the second question is yes in cases 2, 3, and 6. The collective probability of these cases is 1/5 + 1/5 + 1/10 = 1/2.

1/10 over 1/2 is 1/5.

I didn't quite understand the verbal arguments well enough to confidently evaluate them directly (though argument 2 seems to hit the correct applause buttons), but I diagrammed out the options on a spreadsheet and got the same answer as argument 2.

Essentially the reason argument 1 is wrong is because in enumerating the different possible outcomes compatible with the response given, the hand with 2 aces should receive half the weight of the other hands containing the ace of spades, since it will only yield a "yes" half the time, and therefore has ... (read more)

In some detail:

edit: I haven't looked at the post in detail, but I think Morendil did basically the same thing I do here.

Let S count the number of aces of spades you draw, and H the number of aces of hearts. Select one ace randomly from your hand, with equal probability of selection each of the aces you hold. Let R = 1 if the ace of spades is selected, and 0 otherwise. By Baye's Rule we have:

P(S+H=2 | S+H >= 1 and R=1)= [ P(S+H=2) * P(S+H >= 1 and R=1 | S+H=2) ] / [ P(S+H >= 1 and R=1) ]

P(S+H=2) = 1/6 since there are 4 choose 2 = 6 possibl... (read more)

There's something interesting about the answer "I wrote a script to figure it out". Does that amount to giving a frequentist answer to a Bayesian question, or am I all wet ?

If the latter, what does your example teach about frequentist vs Bayesian reasoning, Eliezer ?

1Matt_Simpson
Running a script is just coming up with a model of the problem where our uncertainties about the problem are isomorphic, or at least approximately isomorphic, to our uncertainties about the model. In this case, our uncertainties about the model are our uncertainties about the underlying algorithms in the script. It's just like dropping a flat disc on a Plinko board and saying "hey, at each junction the disc could go either way with roughly equal probability, so this is like a coin flip, so let's simulate 1000 games of Plinko with coin flips and see what happens." I don't see it teaching anything about the difference, but if it does I'd be glad to hear it. I think cousin it is right: this problem, like the monty hall problem, hinges on the difference between choosing something and choosing something randomly. Frequentists are well aware of the monty hall problem - it was one of my assigned problems last semester in my stat theory course, straight out of the text (Statistical Inference, 2nd edition, by Casella and Berger).

(EDITED) Computing this the long way, by straightforward application of the product rule, yields probability 1/5.

There is a shortcut corresponding to argument 2. Call H the hypothesis that you have two aces, and E the evidence constituted by my confirming the ace I pick at random is spades. It turns out that P(E|H)=P(E|!H), so the evidence can't change my probability assignment. P(E|H) = P(spades | 2 aces) = 1/2. P(E|!H) = P (spades | 1 ace) = 1/2.

Now do it the long way: I start from P(2A,SR|A), that is, the probability that I hold two aces AND that I chos... (read more)

If the player has the SPADE:

  • 1/3 of the time, he also has the HEART.
  • 2/3 of the time he doesn't, and so must choose the SPADE.
  • 1/6 of the time he chooses the SPADE though he did have the HEART.

So 5/6 of the time he chooses the SPADE, but only 1/6 of the time does he choose the SPADE while having the HEART.

Thus, the chance of him having the HEART when he has chosen the SPADE is 1/5.

V guvax gur reebe vf urer.

V nfx lbh "Qb lbh unir na npr?" Lbh erfcbaq "Lrf." Gur cebonovyvgl lbh ubyq obgu nprf vf 1/5:

Engure gur cebonovyvgl lbh unir gur n fcrpvsvp npr vf 1/2 naq gur cbffvovyvgl gerr sbe rnpu npr frcnengryl tvirf n 1/3 punapr bs univat obgu nprf. Tvivat n 2/6 be 1/3 punapr bs univat obgu nprf va gbgny.

Va fubeg, vg vf abg rdhvyvxryl gb unir rnpu bs gur 5 pbzovangvbaf.

Edit: This is wrong feel free to ignore.

My posterior probability that you hold two aces should be the same either way

Yes, but the posterior probability is 1/3, not 1/5. p(two aces|AH) = 1/3 (As the possible options are, AH+AS, AH+2D, AH+2C) p(two aces|AS) = 1/3 (AS+AH, AS+2D, AS+2C)

However, if you had interpreted argument 2 as asking p(two aces|ace of hearts OR ace of spades) you would end up with 1/5, which is the same result as the prior p(two aces|have an ace). I think the fallacious reasoning here is that conditioning on the disjunction of having either ace, p(both aces|AH OR AS) = 1/5, does... (read more)

1Unknowns
When you say that the posterior probability is 1/3, this depends on the three combinations being equally likely, but as I said in my other comment, they are not equally likely, given your way of obtaining the information.
2wkvong
I see, your solution seems correct now in retrospect. I mistook scenario 2 for being exactly the same as scenario 1, but the two situations where you are not holding the other ace are indeed twice as likely as having both aces (due to selecting the ace at random), so the answer should be 1/5. Looks like I should brush up on my basic probability...
[-]Sly00

It seems that either: argument 1 is correct or scenario 1 is not valid?

4timtyler
Note that in scenario 1 there is no random choosing. In the main question, there's the possibility of holding AS - but randomly not choosing it. That never happens in scenario 1. So: it seems a bit different...
1Sly
Ah, I see where I went wrong now. Thanks!