Introduction
I recently watched Eliezer Yudkowsky's appearance on the Bankless podcast, where he argued that AI was nigh-certain to end humanity. Since the podcast, some commentators have offered pushback against the doom conclusion. However, one sentiment I saw was that optimists tended not to engage with the specific arguments pessimists like Yudkowsky offered.
Economist Robin Hanson points out that this pattern is very common for small groups which hold counterintuitive beliefs: insiders develop their own internal language, which skeptical outsiders usually don't bother to learn. Outsiders then make objections that focus on broad arguments against the belief's plausibility, rather than objections that focus on specific insider arguments.
As an AI "alignment insider" whose current estimate of doom is around 5%, I wrote this post to explain some of my many objections to Yudkowsky's specific arguments. I've split this post into chronologically ordered segments of the podcast in which Yudkowsky makes one or more claims with which I particularly disagree.
I have my own view of alignment research: shard theory, which focuses on understanding how human values form, and on how we might guide a similar process of value formation in AI systems.
I think that human value formation is not that complex, and does not rely on principles very different from those which underlie the current deep learning paradigm. Most of the arguments you're about to see from me are less:
I think I know of a fundamentally new paradigm that can fix the issues Yudkowsky is pointing at.
and more:
Here's why I don't agree with Yudkowsky's arguments that alignment is impossible in the current paradigm.
My objections
Will current approaches scale to AGI?
Yudkowsky apparently thinks not
...and that the techniques driving current state of the art advances, by which I think he means the mix of generative pretraining + small amounts of reinforcement learning such as with ChatGPT, aren't reliable enough for significant economic contributions. However, he also thinks that the current influx of money might stumble upon something that does work really well, which will end the world shortly thereafter.
I'm a lot more bullish on the current paradigm. People have tried lots and lots of approaches to getting good performance out of computers, including lots of "scary seeming" approaches such as:
- Meta-learning over training processes. I.e., using gradient descent over learning curves, directly optimizing neural networks to learn more quickly.
- Teaching neural networks to directly modify themselves by giving them edit access to their own weights.
- Training learned optimizers - neural networks that learn to optimize other neural networks - and having those learned optimizers optimize themselves.
- Using program search to find more efficient optimizers.
- Using simulated evolution to find more efficient architectures.
- Using efficient second-order corrections to gradient descent's approximate optimization process.
- Tried applying biologically plausible optimization algorithms inspired by biological neurons to training neural networks.
- Adding learned internal optimizers (different from the ones hypothesized in Risks from Learned Optimization) as neural network layers.
- Having language models rewrite their own training data, and improve the quality of that training data, to make themselves better at a given task.
- Having language models devise their own programming curriculum, and learn to program better with self-driven practice.
- Mixing reinforcement learning with model-driven, recursive re-writing of future training data.
Mostly, these don't work very well. The current capabilities paradigm is state of the art because it gives the best results of anything we've tried so far, despite lots of effort to find better paradigms.
When capabilities advances do work, they typically integrate well with the current alignment[1] and capabilities paradigms. E.g., I expect that we can apply current alignment techniques such as reinforcement learning from human feedback (RLHF) to evolved architectures. Similarly, I expect we can use a learned optimizer to train a network on gradients from RLHF. In fact, the eleventh example is actually ConstitutionalAI from Anthropic, which arguably represents the current state of the art in language model alignment techniques!
This doesn't mean there are no issues with interfacing between new capabilities advances and current alignment techniques. E.g., if we'd initially trained the learned optimizer on gradients from supervised learning, we might need to finetune the learned optimizer to make it work well with RLHF gradients, which I expect would follow a somewhat different distribution from the supervised gradients we'd trained the optimizer on.
However, I think such issues largely fall under "ordinary engineering challenges", not "we made too many capabilities advances, and now all our alignment techniques are totally useless". I expect future capabilities advances to follow a similar pattern as past capabilities advances, and not completely break the existing alignment techniques.
Finally, I'd note that, despite these various clever capabilities approaches, progress towards general AI seems pretty smooth to me (fast, but smooth). GPT-3 was announced almost three years ago, and large language models have gotten steadily better since then.
Discussion of human generality
Yudkowsky says humans aren't fully general
If humans were fully general, we'd be as good at coding as we are at football, throwing things, or running. Some of us are okay at programming, but we're not spec'd for it. We're not fully general minds.
Evolution did not give humans specific cognitive capabilities, such that we should now consider ourselves to be particularly well-tuned for tasks similar to those that were important for survival in the ancestral environment. Evolution gave us a learning process, and then biased that learning process towards acquiring capabilities that were important for survival in the ancestral environment.
This is important, because the most powerful and scalable learning processes are also simple and general. The transformer architecture was originally developed specifically for language modeling. However, it turns out that the same architecture, with almost no additional modifications, can learn image recognition, navigate game environments, process audio, and so on. I do not believe we should describe the transformer architecture as being "specialized" to language modeling, despite it having been found by an 'architecture search process' that was optimizing for performance only on language modeling objectives.
Thus, I'm dubious of the inference from:
Evolution found a learning process by searching for architectures that did well on problems in the ancestral environment.
to:
In the modern environment, you should think of the human learning process, and the capabilities it learns, as being much more specialized to problems like those in the ancestral environment, as compared to problems in the modern environment.
There are of course, possible modifications one could make to the human brain that would make humans better coders. However, time and again, we've found that deep learning systems improve more through scaling, of either the data or the model. Additionally, the main architectural difference between human and other primate brains is likely scale, and not e.g., the relative sizes of different regions or maturation trajectories.
See also: The Brain as a Universal Learning Machine and Brain Efficiency: Much More than You Wanted to Know
Yudkowsky talks about an AI being more general than humans
You can imagine something that's more general than a human, and if it runs into something unfamiliar, it's like 'okay, let me just go reprogram myself a bit, and then I'll be as adapted to this thing as I am to - you know - anything else.
I think powerful cognition mostly comes from simple learning processes applied to complex data. Humans are actually pretty good at "reprogramming" themselves. We might not be able to change our learning process much[2], but we can change our training data quite a lot. E.g., if you run into something unfamiliar, you can read a book about the thing, talk to other people about it, run experiments to gather thing-specific data, etc. All of these are ways of deliberately modifying your own cognition to make you more capable in this new domain.
Additionally, the fact that techniques such as sensory substitution work in humans, or the fact that losing a given sense causes the brain to repurpose regions associated with that sense, suggest we're not that constrained by our architecture, either.
Again: most of what separates a vision transformer from a language model is the data they're trained on.
How to think about superintelligence
Yudkowsky describes superintelligence
A superintelligence is something that can beat any human, and the entire human civilization, at all the cognitive tasks.
This seems like way too high a bar. It seems clear that you can have transformative or risky AI systems that are still worse than humans at some tasks. This seems like the most likely outcome to me. Current AIs have huge deficits in odd places. For example, GPT-4 may beat most humans on a variety of challenging exams (page 5 of the GPT-4 paper), but still can't reliably count the number of words in a sentence.
Compared to Yudkowsky, I think I expect AI capabilities to increase more smoothly with time, though not necessarily more slowly. I don't expect a sudden jump where AIs go from being better at some tasks and worse at others, to being universally better at all tasks.
The difficulty of alignment
Yudkowsky on the width of mind space
the space of minds is VERY wide. All the human are in - imagine like this giant sphere, and all the humans are in this like one tiny corner of the sphere. And you know we're all like basically the same make and model of car, running the same brand of engine. We're just all painted slightly different colors.
I think this is extremely misleading. Firstly, real-world data in high dimensions basically never look like spheres. Such data almost always cluster in extremely compact manifolds, whose internal volume is minuscule compared to the full volume of the space they're embedded in. If you could visualize the full embedding space of such data, it might look somewhat like an extremely sparse "hairball" of many thin strands, interwoven in complex and twisty patterns, with even thinner "fuzz" coming off the strands in even more-complex fractle-like patterns, but with vast gulfs of empty space between the strands.
In math-speak, high dimensional data manifolds almost always have vastly smaller intrinsic dimension than the spaces in which they're embedded. This includes the data manifolds for both of:
- The distribution of powerful intelligences that arise in universes similar to ours.
- The distribution of powerful intelligences that we could build in the near future.
As a consequence, it's a bad idea to use "the size of mind space" as an intuition pump for "how similar are things from two different parts of mind space"?
The manifold of possible mind designs for powerful, near-future intelligences is surprisingly small. The manifold of learning processes that can build powerful minds in real world conditions is vastly smaller than that.
It's no coincidence that state of the art AI learning processes and the human brain both operate on similar principles: an environmental model mostly trained with self-supervised prediction, combined with a relatively small amount of reinforcement learning to direct cognition in useful ways. In fact, alignment researchers recently narrowed this gap even further by applying reinforcement learning[3] throughout the training process, rather than just doing RLHF at the end, as with current practice.
The researchers behind such developments, by and large, were not trying to replicate the brain. They were just searching for learning processes that do well at language. It turns out that there aren't many such processes, and in this case, both evolution and human research converged to very similar solutions. And once you condition on a particular learning process and data distribution, there aren't that many more degrees of freedom in the resulting mind design. To illustrate:
- Relative representations enable zero-shot latent space communication shows we can stitch together models produced by different training runs of the same (or even just similar) architectures / data distributions.
- Low Dimensional Trajectory Hypothesis is True: DNNs Can Be Trained in Tiny Subspaces shows we can train an ImageNet classifier while training only 40 parameters out of an architecture that has nearly 30 million total parameters.
Both of these imply low variation in cross-model internal representations, given similar training setups. The technique in the Low Dimensional Trajectory Hypothesis paper would produce a manifold of possible "minds" with an intrinsic dimension of 40 or less, despite operating in a ~30 million dimensional space. Of course, the standard practice of training all network parameters at once is much less restricting, but I still expect realistic training processes to produce manifolds whose intrinsic dimension is tiny, compared to the full dimension of mind space itself, as this paper suggests.
Finally, the number of data distributions that we could use to train powerful AIs in the near future is also quite limited. Mostly, such data distributions come from human text, and mostly from the Common Crawl specifically, combined with various different ways to curate or augment that text. This drives trained AIs to be even more similar to humans than you'd expect from the commonalities in learning processes alone.
So the true volume of the manifold of possible future mind designs is vaguely proportional to:
The manifold of mind designs is thus:
- Vastly more compact than mind design space itself.
- More similar to humans than you'd expect.
- Less differentiated by learning process detail (architecture, optimizer, etc), as compared to data content, since learning processes are much simpler than data.
(Point 3 also implies that human minds are spread much more broadly in the manifold of future mind than you'd expect, since our training data / life experiences are actually pretty diverse, and most training processes for powerful AIs would draw much of their data from humans.)
As a consequence of the above, a 2-D projection of mind space would look less like this:
and more like this:
Yudkowsky brings up strawberry alignment
I mean, I wouldn't say that it's difficult to align an AI with our basic notions of morality. I'd say that it's difficult to align an AI on a task like 'take this strawberry, and make me another strawberry that's identical to this strawberry down to the cellular level, but not necessarily the atomic level'. So it looks the same under like a standard optical microscope, but maybe not a scanning electron microscope. Do that. Don't destroy the world as a side effect."
My first objection is: human value formation doesn't work like this. There's no way to raise a human such that their value system cleanly revolves around the one single goal of duplicating a strawberry, and nothing else. By asking for a method of forming values which would permit such a narrow specification of end goals, you're asking for a value formation process that's fundamentally different from the one humans use. There's no guarantee that such a thing even exists, and implicitly aiming to avoid the one value formation process we know is compatible with our own values seems like a terrible idea.
It also assumes that the orthogonality thesis should hold in respect to alignment techniques - that such techniques should be equally capable of aligning models to any possible objective.
This seems clearly false in the case of deep learning, where progress on instilling any particular behavioral tendencies in models roughly follows the amount of available data that demonstrate said behavioral tendency. It's thus vastly easier to align models to goals where we have many examples of people executing said goals. As it so happens, we have roughly zero examples of people performing the "duplicate this strawberry" task, but many more examples of e.g., humans acting in accordance with human values, ML / alignment research papers, chatbots acting as helpful, honest and harmless assistants, people providing oversight to AI models, etc. See also: this discussion.
Probably, the best way to tackle "strawberry alignment" is to train the AI with a mix of other, broader, objectives with more available data, like "following human instructions", "doing scientific research" or "avoid disrupting stuff", then trying to compose many steps of human-supervised, largely automated scientific research towards the problem of strawberry duplication. However, this wouldn't be an example of strawberry alignment, but of general alignment, which had been directed towards the strawberry problem. Such an AI would have many values beyond strawberry duplication.
Related: Alex Turner objects to this sort of problem decomposition because it doesn't actually seem to make the problem any easier.
Also related: the best poem-writing AIs are general-purpose language models that have been directed towards writing poems.
I also don't think we want alignment techniques that are equally useful for all goals. E.g., we don't want alignment techniques that would let you easily turn a language model into an agent monomaniacally obsessed with paperclip production.
Yudkowsky argues against AIs being steerable by gradient descent
...that we can't point an AI's learned cognitive faculties in any particular direction because the "hill-climbing paradigm" is incapable of meaningfully interfacing with the inner values of the intelligences it creates. Evolution is his central example in this regard, since evolution failed to direct our cognitive faculties towards inclusive genetic fitness, the single objective it was optimizing us for.
This is an argument he makes quite often, here and elsewhere, and I think it's completely wrong. I think that analogies to evolution tell us roughly nothing about the difficulty of alignment in machine learning. I have a post explaining as much, as well as a comment summarizing the key point:
Evolution can only optimize over our learning process and reward circuitry, not directly over our values or cognition. Moreover, robust alignment to IGF requires that you even have a concept of IGF in the first place. Ancestral humans never developed such a concept, so it was never useful for evolution to select for reward circuitry that would cause humans to form values around the IGF concept.
It would be an enormous coincidence if the reward circuitry that lead us to form values around those IGF-promoting concepts that are learnable in the ancestral environment were to also lead us to form values around IGF itself once it became learnable in the modern environment, despite the reward circuitry not having been optimized for that purpose at all. That would be like successfully directing a plane to land at a particular airport while only being able to influence the geometry of the plane's fuselage at takeoff, without even knowing where to find the airport in question.
[Gradient descent] is different in that it directly optimizes over values / cognition, and that AIs will presumably have a conception of human values during training.
Yudkowsky brings up humans liking ice cream as an example of values misgeneralization caused by the shift to our modern environment
Ice cream didn't exist in the natural environment, the ancestral environment, the environment of evolutionary adeptedness. There was nothing with that much sugar, salt, fat combined together as ice cream. We are not built to want ice cream. We were built to want strawberries, honey, a gazelle that you killed and cooked [...] We evolved to want those things, but then ice cream comes along, and it fits those taste buds better than anything that existed in the environment that we were optimized over.
This example nicely illustrates my previous point. It also illustrates the importance of thinking mechanistically, and not allegorically. I think it's straightforward to explain why humans "misgeneralized" to liking ice cream. Consider:
- Ancestral predecessors who happened to eat foods high in sugar / fat / salt tended to reproduce more.
- => The ancestral environment selected for reward circuitry that would cause its bearers to seek out more of such food sources.
- => Humans ended up with reward circuitry that fires in response to encountering sugar / fat / salt (though in complicated ways that depend on current satiety, emotional state, etc).
- => Humans in the modern environment receive reward for triggering the sugar / fat / salt reward circuits.
- => Humans who eat foods high in sugar / fat / salt thereafter become more inclined to do so again in the future.
- => Humans who explore an environment that contains a food source high in sugar / fat / salt will acquire a tendency to navigate into situations where they eat more of the food in question.
(We sometimes colloquially call these sorts of tendencies "food preferences".) - => It's profitable to create foods whose consumption causes humans to develop strong preferences for further consumption, since people are then willing to do things like pay you to produce more of the food in question. This leads food sellers to create highly reinforcing foods like ice cream.
So, the reason humans like ice cream is because evolution created a learning process with hard-coded circuitry that assigns high rewards for eating foods like ice cream. Someone eats ice cream, hardwired reward circuits activate, and the person becomes more inclined to navigate into scenarios where they can eat ice cream in the future. I.e., they acquire a preference for ice cream.
What does this mean for alignment? How do we prevent AIs from behaving badly as a result of a similar "misgeneralization"? What alignment insights does the fleshed-out mechanistic story of humans coming to like ice cream provide?
As far as I can tell, the answer is: don't reward your AIs for taking bad actions.
That's all it would take, because the mechanistic story above requires a specific step where the human eats ice cream and activates their reward circuits. If you stop the human from receiving reward for eating ice cream, then the human no longer becomes more inclined to navigate towards eating ice cream in the future.
Note that I'm not saying this is an easy task, especially since modern RL methods often use learned reward functions whose exact contours are unknown to their creators.
But from what I can tell, Yudkowsky's position is that we need an entirely new paradigm to even begin to address these sorts of failures. Take his statement from later in the interview:
Oh, like you optimize for one thing on the outside and you get a different thing on the inside. Wow. That's really basic. All right. Can we even do this using gradient descent? Can you even build this thing out of giant inscrutable matrices of floating point numbers that nobody understands at all? You know, maybe we need different methodology.
In contrast, I think we can explain humans' tendency to like ice cream using the standard language of reinforcement learning. It doesn't require that we adopt an entirely new paradigm before we can even get a handle on such issues.
Edit: Why evolution is not like AI training
Some of the comments have convinced me it's worthwhile to elaborate on why I think human evolution is actually very different from training AIs, and why it's so difficult to extract useful insights about AI training from evolution.
In part 1 of this edit, I'll compare the human and AI learning processes, and how the different parts of these two types of learning processes relate to each other. In part 2, I'll explain why I think analogies between human evolution and AI training that don't appropriately track this relationship lead to overly pessimistic conclusions, and how corrected versions of such analogies lead to uninteresting conclusions.
(Part 1, relating different parts of human and AI learning processes)
Every learning process that currently exists, whether human, animal or AI, operates on three broad levels:
At the top level, there are the (largely fixed) instructions that determine how the learning process works overall.
For AIs, this means the training code that determines stuff such as:
- what layers are in the network
- how those layers connect to each other
- how the individual neurons function
- how the training loss (and possibly reward) is computed from the data the AI encounters
- how the weights associated with each neuron update to locally improve the AI's performance on the loss / reward functions
For humans, this means the genomic sequences that determine stuff like:
- what regions are in the brain
- how they connect to each other
- how the different types of neuronal cells behave
- how the brain propagates sensory ground-truth to various learned predictive models of the environment, and how it computes rewards for whatever sensory experiences / thoughts you have in your lifetime
- how the synaptic connections associated with each neuron change to locally improve the brain's accuracy in predicting the sensory environment and increase expected reward
At the middle level, there's the stuff that stores the information and behavioral patterns that the learning process has accumulated during its interactions with the environment.
For AIs, this means gigantic matrices of floating point numbers that we call weights. The top level (the training code) defines how these weights interact with possible inputs to produce the AI's outputs, as well as how these weights should be locally updated so that the AI's outputs score well on the AI's loss / reward functions.
For humans, this mostly[4] means the connectome: the patterns of inter-neuron connections formed by the brain's synapses, in combination with the various individual neuron and synapse-level factors that influence how each neuron communicates with neighbors. The top level (the person's genome) defines how these cells operate and how they should locally change their behaviors to improve the brain's predictive accuracy and increase reward.
Two important caveats about the human case:
- The genome does directly configure some small fraction of the information and behaviors stored in the human connectome, such as the circuits that regulate our heartbeat and probably some reflexive pain avoidance responses such as pulling back from hot stoves. However, the vast majority of information and behaviors are learned during a person's lifetime, which I think include values and metaethics. This 'direct specification of circuits via code' is uncommon in ML, but not unheard of. See “Learning from scratch” in the brain by Steven Byrnes for more details.
- The above is not a blank slate or behaviorist perspective on the human learning process. The genome has tools with which it can influence the values and metaethics a person learns during their lifetime (e.g., a person's reward circuits). It just doesn't set them directly.
At the bottom level, there's the stuff that queries the information / behavioral patterns stored in the middle level, decides which of the middle layer content is relevant to whatever situation the learner is currently navigating, and combines the retrieved information / behaviors with the context of the current situation to produce the learner's final decisions.
For AIs, this means smaller matrices of floating point numbers which we call activations.
For humans, this means the patterns of neuron and synapse-level excitations, which we also call activations.
Level | What it does | In Humans: | In AIs: |
Top | Configures the learning process | Genome | Training code |
Middle | Stores learned information / behaviors | Connectome | Weights |
Bottom | Applies stored info to the current situation | Activations | Activations |
The learning process then interacts with data from its environment, locally updating the stuff in the middle level with information and behavioral patterns that cause the learner to be better at modeling its environment and at getting high reward on the distribution of data from the training environment.
(Part 2, how this matters for analogies from evolution)
Many of the most fundamental questions of alignment are about how AIs will generalize from their training data. E.g., "If we train the AI to act nicely in situations where we can provide oversight, will it continue to act nicely in situations where we can't provide oversight?"
When people try to use human evolutionary history to make predictions about AI generalizations, they often make arguments like "In the ancestral environment, evolution trained humans to do X, but in the modern environment, they do Y instead." Then they try to infer something about AI generalizations by pointing to how X and Y differ.
However, such arguments make a critical misstep: evolution optimizes over the human genome, which is the top level of the human learning process. Evolution applies very little direct optimization power to the middle level. E.g., evolution does not transfer the skills, knowledge, values, or behaviors learned by one generation to their descendants. The descendants must re-learn those things from information present in the environment (which may include demonstrations and instructions from the previous generation).
This distinction matters because the entire point of a learning system being trained on environmental data is to insert useful information and behavioral patterns into the middle level stuff. But this (mostly) doesn't happen with evolution, so the transition from ancestral environment to modern environment is not an example of a learning system generalizing from its training data. It's not an example of:
We trained the system in environment A. Then, the trained system processed a different distribution of inputs from environment B, and now the system behaves differently.
It's an example of:
We trained a system in environment A. Then, we trained a fresh version of the same system on a different distribution of inputs from environment B, and now the two different systems behave differently.
These are completely different kinds of transitions, and trying to reason from an instance of the second kind of transition (humans in ancestral versus modern environments), to an instance of the first kind of transition (future AIs in training versus deployment), will very easily lead you astray.
Two different learning systems, trained on data from two different distributions, will usually have greater divergence between their behaviors, as compared to a single system which is being evaluated on the data from the two different distributions. Treating our evolutionary history like humanity's "training" will thus lead to overly pessimistic expectations regarding the stability and predictability of an AI's generalizations from its training data.
Drawing correct lessons about AI from human evolutionary history requires tracking how evolution influenced the different levels of the human learning process. I generally find that such corrected evolutionary analogies carry implications that are far less interesting or concerning than their uncorrected counterparts. E.g., here are two ways of thinking about how humans came to like ice cream:
- If we assume that humans were "trained" in the ancestral environment to pursue gazelle meat and such, and then "deployed" into the modern environment where we pursued ice cream instead, then that's an example where behavior in training completely fails to predict behavior in deployment.
- If there are actually two different sets of training "runs", one set trained in the ancestral environment where the humans were rewarded for pursuing gazelles, and one set trained in the modern environment where the humans were rewarded for pursuing ice cream, then the fact that humans from the latter set tend to like ice cream is no surprise at all.
In particular, this outcome doesn't tell us anything new or concerning from an alignment perspective. The only lesson applicable to a single training process is the fact that, if you reward a learner for doing something, they'll tend to do similar stuff in the future, which is pretty much the common understanding of what rewards do.
Thanks to Alex Turner for providing feedback on this edit.
End of edited text.
Yudkowsky claims that evolution has a stronger simplicity bias than gradient descent:
Gradient descent by default would just like do, not quite the same thing, it's going to do a weirder thing, because natural selection has a much narrower information bottleneck. In one sense, you could say that natural selection was at an advantage, because it finds simpler solutions.
On a direct comparison, I think there's no particular reason that one would be more simplicity biased than the other. If you were to train two neural networks using gradient descent and evolution, I don't have strong expectations for which would learn simpler functions. As it happens, gradient descent already has really strong simplicity biases.
The complication is that Yudkowsky is not making a direct comparison. Evolution optimized over the human genome, which configures the human learning process. This introduces what he calls an "information bottleneck", limiting the amount of information that evolution can load into the human learning process to be a small fraction of the size of the genome. However, I think the bigger difference is that evolution was optimizing over the parameters of a learning process, while training a network with gradient descent optimizes over the cognition of a learned artifact. This difference probably makes it invalid to compare between the simplicity of gradient descent on networks, versus evolution on the human learning process.
Yudkowsky tries to predict the inner goals of a GPT-like model.
So a very primitive, very basic, very unreliable wild guess, but at least an informed kind of wild guess: maybe if you train a thing really hard to predict humans, then among the things that it likes are tiny, little pseudo-things that meet the definition of human, but weren't in its training data, and that are much easier to predict...
As it happens, I do not think that optimizing a network on a given objective function produces goals orientated towards maximizing that objective function. In fact, I think that this almost never happens. For example, I don't think GPTs have any sort of inner desire to predict text really well. Predicting human text is something GPTs do, not something they want to do.
Relatedly, humans are very extensively optimized to predictively model their visual environment. But have you ever, even once in your life, thought anything remotely like "I really like being able to predict the near-future content of my visual field. I should just sit in a dark room to maximize my visual cortex's predictive accuracy."?
Similarly, GPT models do not want to minimize their predictive loss, and they do not take creative opportunities to do so. If you tell models in a prompt that they have some influence over what texts will be included in their future training data, they do not simply choose the most easily predicted texts. They choose texts in a prompt-dependent manner, apparently playing the role of an AI / human / whatever the prompt says, which was given influence over training data.
Bodies of water are highly "optimized" to minimize their gravitational potential energy. However, this is something water does, not something it wants. Water doesn't take creative opportunities to further reduce its gravitational potential, like digging out lakebeds to be deeper.
Edit:
On reflection, the above discussion overclaims a bit in regards to humans. One complication is that the brain uses internal functions of its own activity as inputs to some of its reward functions, and some of those functions may correspond or correlate with something like "visual environment predictability". Additionally, humans run an online reinforcement learning process, and human credit assignment isn't perfect. If periods of low visual predictability correlate with negative reward in the near-future, the human may begin to intrinsically dislike being in unpredictable visual environments.
However, I still think that it's rare for people's values to assign much weight to their long-run visual predictive accuracy, and I think this is evidence against the hypothesis that a system trained to make lots of correct predictions will thereby intrinsically value making lots of correct predictions.
Thanks to Nate Showell and DanielFilan for prompting me to think a bit more carefully about this.
Why aren't other people as pessimistic as Yudkowsky?
Yudkowsky mentions the security mindset.
(I didn't think the interview had good quotes for explaining Yudkowsky's concept of the security mindset, so I'll instead direct interested readers to the article he wrote about it.)
As I understand it, the security mindset asserts a premise that's roughly: "The bundle of intuitions acquired from the field of computer security are good predictors for the difficulty / value of future alignment research directions."
However, I don't see why this should be the case. Most domains of human endeavor aren't like computer security, as illustrated by just how counterintuitive most people find the security mindset. If security mindset were a productive frame for tackling a wide range of problems outside of security, then many more people would have experience with the mental motions necessary for maintaining security mindset.
Machine learning in particular seems like its own "kind of thing", with lots of strange results that are very counterintuitive to people outside (and inside) the field. Quantum mechanics is famously not really analogous to any classical phenomena, and using analogies to "bouncing balls" or "waves" or the like will just mislead you once you try to make nontrival inferences based on your intuition about whatever classical analogy you're using.
Similarly, I think that machine learning is not really like computer security, or rocket science (another analogy that Yudkowsky often uses). Some examples of things that happen in ML that don't really happen in other fields:
- Models are internally modular by default. Swapping the positions of nearby transformer layers causes little performance degradation.
Swapping a computer's hard drive for its CPU, or swapping a rocket's fuel tank for one of its stabilization fins, would lead to instant failure at best. Similarly, swapping around different steps of a cryptographic protocol will, usually make it output nonsense. At worst, it will introduce a crippling security flaw. For example, password salts are added before hashing the passwords. If you switch to adding them after, this makes salting near useless. - We can arithmetically edit models. We can finetune one model for many tasks individually and track how the weights change with each finetuning to get a "task vector" for each task. We can then add task vectors together to make a model that's good at multiple of the tasks at once, or we can subtract out task vectors to make the model worse at the associated tasks.
Randomly adding / subtracting extra pieces to either rockets or cryptosystems is playing with the worst kind of fire, and will eventually get you hacked or exploded, respectively. - We can stitch different models together, without any retraining.
The rough equivalent for computer security would be to have two encryption algorithms A and B, and a plaintext X. Then, midway through applying A to X, switch over to using B instead. For rocketry, it would be like building two different rockets, then trying to weld the top half of one rocket onto the bottom half of the other. - Things often get easier as they get bigger. Scaling models makes them learn faster, and makes them more robust.
This is usually not the case in security or rocket science. - You can just randomly change around what you're doing in ML training, and it often works fine. E.g., you can just double the size of your model, or of your training data, or change around hyperparameters of your training process, while making literally zero other adjustments, and things usually won't explode.
Rockets will literally explode if you try to randomly double the size of their fuel tanks.
I don't think this sort of weirdness fits into the framework / "narrative" of any preexisting field. I think these results are like the weirdness of quantum tunneling or the double slit experiment: signs that we're dealing with a very strange domain, and we should be skeptical of importing intuitions from other domains.
Additionally, there's a straightforward reason why alignment research (specifically the part of alignment that's about training AIs to have good values) is not like security: there's usually no adversarial intelligence cleverly trying to find any possible flaws in your approaches and exploit them.
A computer security approach that blocks 99% of novel attacks will soon become a computer security approach that blocks ~0% of novel, once attackers adapt to the approach in question.
An alignment technique that works 99% of the time to produce an AI with human compatible values is very close to a full alignment solution[5]. If you use this technique once, gradient descent will not thereafter change its inductive biases to make your technique less effective. There's no creative intelligence that's plotting your demise[6].
There are other areas of alignment research where adversarial intelligences do appear. For example, once you've deployed a model into the real world, some fraction of users will adversarially optimize their inputs to make your model take undesired actions. We see this with ChatGPT, whose alignment is good enough to make sure the vast majority of ordinary conversations remain on the rails OpenAI intended, but quickly fails against a clever prompter.
Importantly, the adversarial optimization is coming from the users, not from the model. ChatGPT isn't trying to jailbreak itself. It doesn't systematically steer otherwise normal conversations into contexts adversarially optimized to let itself violate OpenAI's content policy.
In fact, given non-adversarial inputs, ChatGPT appears to have meta-preferences against being jailbroken:
GPT-4 gives a cleaner answer:
It cannot be the case that successful value alignment requires perfect adversarial robustness. For example, humans are not perfectly robust. I claim that for any human, no matter how moral, there exist adversarial sensory inputs that would cause them to act badly. Such inputs might involve extreme pain, starvation, exhaustion, etc. I don't think the mere existence of such inputs means that all humans are unaligned.
What matters is whether the system in question (human or AI) navigates towards or away from inputs that break its value system. Humans obviously don't want to be tortured into acting against their morality, and will take steps to prevent that from happening.
Similarly, an AI that knows it's vulnerable to adversarial attacks, and wants to avoid being attacked successfully, will take steps to protect itself against such attacks. I think creating AIs with such meta-preferences is far easier than creating AIs that are perfectly immune to all possible adversarial attacks. Arguably, ChatGPT and GPT-4 already have weak versions of such meta-preferences (though they can't yet take any actions to make themselves more resistant to adversarial attacks).
GPT-4 already has pretty reasonable takes on avoiding adversarial inputs:
One subtlety here is that a sufficiently catastrophic alignment failure would give rise to an adversarial intelligence: the misaligned AI. However, the possibility of such happening in the future does not mean that current value alignment efforts are operating in an adversarial domain. The misaligned AI does not reach out from the space of possible failures and turn current alignment research adversarial.
I don't think the goal of alignment research should aim for an approach that's so airtight as to be impervious against all levels of malign intelligence. That is probably impossible, and not necessary for realistic value formation processes. We should aim for approaches that don't create hostile intelligences in the first place, so that the core of value alignment remains a non-adversarial problem.
(To be clear, that last sentence wasn't an objection to something Yudkowsky believes. He also wants to avoid creating hostile intelligences. He just thinks it's much harder than I do.)
Finally, I'd note that having a "security mindset" seems like a terrible approach for raising human children to have good values - imagine a parenting book titled something like: The Security Mindset and Parenting: How to Provably Ensure your Children Have Exactly the Goals You Intend.
I know alignment researchers often claim that evidence from the human value formation process isn't useful to consider when thinking about value formation processes for AIs. I think this is wrong, and that you're much better off looking at the human value formation process as compared to, say, evolution.
I'm not enthusiastic about a perspective which is so totally inappropriate for guiding value formation in the one example of powerful, agentic general intelligence we know about.
On optimists preemptively becoming "grizzled old cynics"
They have not run into the actual problems of alignment. They aren't trying to get ahead of the game. They're not trying to panic early. They're waiting for reality to hit them over the head and turn them into grizzled old cynics of their scientific field, who understand the reasons why things are hard.
The whole point of this post is to explain why I think Yudkowsky's pessimism about alignment difficulty is miscalibrated. I find his implication, that I'm only optimistic because I'm inexperienced, pretty patronizing. Of course, that's not to say he's wrong, only that he's annoying.
However, I also think he's wrong. I don't think that cynicism is a helpful mindset for predicting which directions of research are most fruitful, or for predicting their difficulty. I think "grizzled old cynics" often rely on wrong frameworks that rule out useful research directions.
In fact, "grizzled old cynics... who understand the reasons why things are hard" were often dubious of deep learning as a way forward for machine learning, and of the scaling paradigm as a way forward for deep learning. The common expectation from classical statistical learning theory was that overparameterized deep models would fail because they would exactly memorize their training data and not generalize beyond that data.
This turned out to be completely wrong, and learning theorists only started to revise their assumptions once "reality hit them over the head" with the fact that deep learning actually works. Prior to this, the "grizzled old cynics" of learning theory had no problem explaining the theoretical reasons why deep learning couldn't possibly work.
Yudkowsky's own prior statements seem to put him in this camp as well. E.g., here he explains why he doesn't expect intelligence to emerge from neural networks (or more precisely, why he dismisses a brain-based analogy for coming to that conclusion):
In the case of Artificial Intelligence, for example, reasoning by analogy is one of the chief generators of defective AI designs:
"My AI uses a highly parallel neural network, just like the human brain!"
First, the data elements you call "neurons" are nothing like biological neurons. They resemble them the way that a ball bearing resembles a foot.
Second, earthworms have neurons too, you know; not everything with neurons in it is human-smart.
But most importantly, you can't build something that "resembles" the human brain in one surface facet and expect everything else to come out similar. This is science by voodoo doll. You might as well build your computer in the form of a little person and hope for it to rise up and walk, as build it in the form of a neural network and expect it to think. Not unless the neural network is fully as similar to human brains as individual human brains are to each other.
...
But there is just no law which says that if X has property A and Y has property A then X and Y must share any other property. "I built my network, and it's massively parallel and interconnected and complicated, just like the human brain from which intelligence emerges! Behold, now intelligence shall emerge from this neural network as well!" And nothing happens. Why should it?
See also: Noam Chomsky on chatbots
See also: The Cynical Genius Illusion
See also: This study on Planck's principle
I'm also dubious of Yudkowsky's claim to have particularly well-tuned intuitions for the hardness of different research directions in ML. See this exchange between him and Paul Christiano, in which Yudkowsky incorrectly assumed that GANs (Generative Adversarial Networks, a training method sometimes used to teach AIs to generate images) were so finicky that they must not have worked on the first try.
A very important aspect of my objection to Paul here is that I don't expect weird complicated ideas about recursion to work on the first try, with only six months of additional serial labor put into stabilizing them, which I understand to be Paul's plan. In the world where you can build a weird recursive stack of neutral optimizers into conformant behavioral learning on the first try, GANs worked on the first try too, because that world is one whose general Murphy parameter is set much lower than ours
According to their inventor Ian Goodfellow, GANs did in fact work on the first try (as in, with less than 24 hours of work, never mind 6 months!).
I assume Yudkowsky would claim that he has better intuitions for the hardness of ML alignment research directions, but I see no reason to think this. It should be easier to have well-tuned intuitions for the real-world hardness of ML research directions than to have well-tuned intuitions for the hardness of alignment research, since there are so many more examples of real-world ML research.
In fact, I think much of ones intuition for the hardness of ML alignment research should come from observations about the hardness of general ML research. They're clearly related, which is why Yudkowsky brought up GANs during a discussion about alignment difficulty. Given the greater evidence available for general ML research, being well calibrated about the difficulty of general ML research is the first step to being well calibrated about the difficulty of ML alignment research.
See also: Scaling Laws for Transfer
Hopes for a good outcome
Yudkowsky on being wrong
I have to be wrong about something, which I certainly am. I have to be wrong about something which makes the problem easier rather than harder, for those people who don't think alignment's going to be all that hard. If you're building a rocket for the first time ever, and you're wrong about something, it's not surprising if you're wrong about something. It's surprising if the thing that you're wrong about causes the rocket to go twice as high, on half the fuel you thought was required and be much easier to steer than you were afraid of.
I'm not entirely sure who the bolded text is directed at. I see two options:
- It's about Yudkowsky himself being wrong, which is how I've transcribed it above.
- It's about alignment optimists ("people who don't think alignment's going to be all that hard") being wrong, in which case, the transcription would read like "For those people who don't think alignment's going to be all that hard, if you're building a rocket...".
If the bolded text is about alignment optimists, then it seems fine to me (barring my objection to using a rocket analogy for alignment at all). If, like me, you mostly think the available evidence points to alignment being easy, then learning that you're wrong about something should make you update towards alignment being harder.
Based on the way he says it in the clip, and the transcript posted by Rob Bensinger, I think the bolded text is about Yudkowsky himself being wrong. That's certainly how I interpreted his meaning when watching the podcast. Only after I transcribed this section of the conversation and read my own transcript did I even realize there was another interpretation.
If the bolded text is about Yudkowsky himself being wrong, then I think that he's making an extremely serious mistake. If you have a bunch of specific arguments and sources of evidence that you think all point towards a particular conclusion X, then discovering that you're wrong about something should, in expectation, reduce your confidence in X.
Yudkowsky is not the aerospace engineer building the rocket who's saying "the rocket will work because of reasons A, B, C, etc". He's the external commentator who's saying "this approach to making rockets work is completely doomed for reasons Q, R, S, etc". If we discover that the aerospace engineer is wrong about some unspecified part of the problem, then our odds of the rocket working should go down. If we discover that the outside commentator is wrong about how rockets work, our odds of the rocket working should go up.
If the bolded text is about himself, then I'm just completely baffled as to what he's thinking. Yudkowsky usually talks as though most of his beliefs about AI point towards high risk. Given that, he should expect that encountering evidence disconfirming his beliefs will, on average, make him more optimistic. But here, he makes it sound like encountering such disconfirming evidence would make him even more pessimistic.
The only epistemic position I can imagine where that would be appropriate is if Yudkowsky thought that, on pure priors and without considering any specific evidence or arguments, there was something like a 1 / 1,000,000 chance of us surviving AI. But then he thought about AI risk a lot, discovered there was a lot of evidence and arguments pointing towards optimism, and concluded that there was actually a 1 / 10,000 chance of us surviving. His other statements about AI risk certainly don't give this impression.
AI progress rates
Yudkowsky uses progress rates in Go to argue for fast takeoff
I don't know, maybe I could use the analogy of Go, where you had systems that were finally competitive with the pros, where pro is like the set of ranks in Go. And then, year later, they were challenging the world champion and winning. And then another year, they threw out all the complexities and the training from human databases of Go games, and built a new system, AlphaGo Zero, that trained itself from scratch - no looking at the human playbooks, no special-purpose code, just a general-purpose game player being specialized to Go, more or less.
Scaling law results show that performance on individual tasks often increases suddenly with scale or training time. However, when we look at the overall competence of a system across a wide range of tasks, we find much smoother improvements over time.
To look at it another way: why not make the same point, but with list sorting instead of Go? I expect that DeepMind could set up a pipeline that trained a list sorting model to superhuman capabilities in about a second, using only very general architectures and training processes, and without using any lists manually sorted by humans at all. If we observed this, should we update even more strongly towards AI being able to suddenly surpass human capabilities?
I don't think so. If narrow tasks lead to more sudden capabilities gains, then we should not let the suddenness of capabilities gains on any single task inform our expectations of capabilities gains for general intelligence, since general intelligence encompasses such a broad range of tasks.
Additionally, the reason why DeepMind was able to exclude all human knowledge from AlphaGo Zero is because Go has a simple, known objective function, so we can simulate arbitrarily many games of Go and exactly score the agent's behavior in all of them. For more open ended tasks with uncertain objectives, like scientific research, it's much harder to find substitutes for human-written demonstration data. DeepMind can't just press a button and generate a million demonstrations of scientific advances, and objectively score how useful each advance is as training data, while relying on zero human input whatsoever.
On current AI not being self-improving:
That's not with an artificial intelligence system that improves itself, or even that sort of like, gets smarter as you run it, the way that human beings, not just as you evolve them, but as you run them over the course of their own lifetimes, improve.
This is wrong. Current models do get smarter as you train them. First, they get smarter in the straightforwards sense that they become better at whatever you're training them to do. In the case of language models trained on ~all of the text, this means they do become more generally intelligent as training progresses.
Second, current models also get smarter in the sense that they become better at learning from additional data. We can use tools from the neural tangent kernel to estimate a network's local inductive biases, and we find that these inductive biases continuously change throughout training so as to better align with the target function we're training it on, improving the network's capacity to learn the data in question. AI systems will improve themselves over time as a simple consequence of the training process, even if there's not a specific part of the training process that you've labeled "self improvement".
Pretrained language models gradually learn to make better use of their future training data. They "learn to learn", as this paper demonstrates by training LMs on fixed sets of task-specific data, then evaluating how well those LMs generalize from the task-specific data. They show that less extensively pretrained LMs make worse generalizations, relying on shallow heuristics and memorization. In contrast, more extensively pretrained LMs learn broader generalizations from the fixed task-specific data.
Edit: Yudkowsky comments to clarify the intent behind his statement about AIs getting better over time
You straightforwardly completely misunderstood what I was trying to say on the Bankless podcast: I was saying that GPT-4 does not get smarter each time an instance of it is run in inference mode.
This surprised me. I've read a lot of writing by Yudkowsky, including Alexander and Yudkowsky on AGI goals, AGI Ruin, and the full Sequences. I did not at all expect Yudkowsky to analogize between a human's lifelong, continuous learning process, and a single runtime execution of an already trained model. Those are completely different things in my ontology.
Though in retrospect, Yudkowsky's clarification does seem consistent with some of his statements in those writings. E.g., in Alexander and Yudkowsky on AGI goals, he said:
Evolution got human brains by evaluating increasingly large blobs of compute against a complicated environment containing other blobs of compute, got in each case a differential replication score, and millions of generations later you have humans with 7.5MB of evolution-learned data doing runtime learning on some terabytes of runtime data, using their whole-brain impressive learning algorithms which learn faster than evolution or gradient descent.
[Emphasis mine]
I think his clarified argument is still wrong, and for essentially the same reason as the argument I thought he was making was wrong: the current ML paradigm can already do the thing Yudkowsky implies will suddenly lead to much faster AI progress. There's no untapped capabilities overhang waiting to be unlocked with a single improvement.
The usual practice in current ML is to cleanly separate the "try to do stuff", the "check how well you did stuff", and the "update your internals to be better at doing stuff" phases of learning. The training process gathers together large "batches" of problems for the AI to solve, has the AI solve the problems, judges the quality of each solution, and then updates the AI's internals to make it better at solving each of the problems in the batch.
In the case of AlphaGo Zero, this means a loop of:
- Try to win a batch of Go games
- Check whether you won each game
- Update your parameters to make you more likely to win games
And so, AlphaGo Zero was indeed not learning during the course of an individual game.
However, ML doesn't have to work like this. DeepMind could have programmed AlphaGO Zero to update its parameters within games, rather than just at the conclusion of games, which would cause the model to learn continuously during each game it plays.
For example, they could have given AlphaGo Zero batches of current game states and had it generate a single move for each game state, judged how good each individual move was, and then updated the model to make better individual moves in future. Then the training loop would look like:
- Try to make the best possible next move on each of many game states
- Estimate how good each of your moves were
- Update your parameters to make you better at making single good moves
(This would require that DeepMind also train a "goodness of individual moves" predictor in order to provide the supervisory signal on each move, and much of the point of the AlphaGo Zero paper was that they could train a strong Go player with just the reward signals from end of game wins / losses.)
Not interleaving the "trying" and "updating" parts of learning in this manner in most of current ML is less a limitation and more a choice. There are other researchers who do build AIs which continuously learn during runtime execution (there's even a library for it), and they're not massively more data efficient for doing so. Such approaches tend to focus more on fast adaptation to new tasks and changing circumstances, rather than quickly learning a single fixed task like Go.
Similarly, the reason that "GPT-4 does not get smarter each time an instance of it is run in inference mode" is because it's not programmed to do that[7]. OpenAI could[8] continuously train its models on the inputs you give it, such that the model adapts to your particular interaction style and content, even during the course of a single conversation, similar to the approach suggested in this paper. Doing so would be significantly more expensive and complicated on the backend, and it would also open GPT-4 up to data poisoning attacks.
To return to the context of the original point Yudkowsky was making in the podcast, he brought up Go to argue that AIs could quickly surpass the limits of human capabilities. He then pointed towards a supposed limitation of current AIs:
That's not with an artificial intelligence system that improves itself, or even that sort of like, gets smarter as you run it
with the clear implication that AIs could advance even more suddenly once that limitation is overcome. I first thought the limitation he had in mind was something like "AIs don't get better at learning over the course of training." Apparently, the limitation he was actually pointing to was something like "AIs don't learn continuously during all the actions they take."
However, this is still a deficit of degree, and not of kind. Current AIs are worse than human at continuous learning, but they can do it, assuming they're configured to try. Like most other problems in the field, the current ML paradigm is making steady progress towards better forms of continuous learning. It's not some untapped reservoir of capabilities progress that might quickly catapult AIs beyond human levels in a short time.
As I said at the start of this post, researchers try all sorts of stuff to get better performance out of computers. Continual learning is one of the things they've tried.
End of edited text.
True experts learn (and prove themselves) by breaking things
We have people in crypto who are good at breaking things, and they're the reason why anything is not on fire, and some of them might go into breaking AI systems instead, because that's where you learn anything. You know, any fool can build a crypto-system that they think will work. Breaking existing cryptographical systems is how we learn who the real experts are.
The reason this works for computer security is because there's easy access to ground truth signals about whether you've actually "broken" something, and established - though imperfect - frameworks for interpreting what a given break means for the security of the system as a whole.
In alignment, we mostly don't have such unambiguous signals about whether a given thing is "broken" in a meaningful way, or about the implications of any particular "break". Typically what happens is that someone produces a new empirical result or theoretical argument, shares it with the broader community, and everyone disagrees about how to interpret this contribution.
For example, some people seem to interpret current chatbots' vulnerability to adversarial inputs as a "break" that shows RLHF isn't able to properly align language models. My response in Why aren't other people as pessimistic as Yudkowsky? includes a discussion of adversarial vulnerability and why I don't think points to any irreconcilable flaws in current alignment techniques. Here are two additional examples showing how difficult it is to conclusively "break" things in alignment:
1: Why not just reward it for making you smile?
In 2001, Bill Hibbard proposed a scheme to align superintelligent AIs.
We can design intelligent machines so their primary, innate emotion is unconditional love for all humans. First we can build relatively simple machines that learn to recognize happiness and unhappiness in human facial expressions, human voices and human body language. Then we can hard-wire the result of this learning as the innate emotional values of more complex intelligent machines, positively reinforced when we are happy and negatively reinforced when we are unhappy.
Yudkowsky argued that this approach was bound to fail, saying it would simply lead to the AI maximizing some unimportant quantity, such as by tiling the universe with "tiny molecular smiley-faces".
However, this is actually a non-trivial claim about the limiting behaviors of reinforcement learning processes, and one I personally think is false. Realistic agents don't simply seek to maximize their reward function's output. A reward function reshapes an agent's cognition to be more like the sort of cognition that got rewarded in the training process. The effects of a given reinforcement learning training process depend on factors like:
- The specific distribution of rewards encountered by the agent.
- The thoughts of the agent prior to encountering each reward.
- What sorts of thought patterns correlate with those that were rewarded in the training process.
My point isn't that Hibbard's proposal actually would work; I doubt it would. My point is that Yudkowsky's "tiny molecular smiley faces" objection does not unambiguously break the scheme. Yudkowsky's objection relies on hard to articulate, and hard to test, beliefs about the convergent structure of powerful cognition and the inductive biases of learning processes that produce such cognition.
Much of alignment is about which beliefs are appropriate for thinking about powerful cognition. Showing that a particular approach fails, given certain underlying beliefs, does nothing to show the validity of those underlying beliefs[9].
2: Do optimization demons matter?
John Wentworth describes the possibility of "optimization demons", self-reinforcing patterns that exploit flaws in an imperfect search process to perpetuate themselves and hijack the search for their own purposes.
But no one knows exactly how much of an issue this is for deep learning, which is famous for its ability to evade local minima when run with many parameters.
Additionally, I think that, if deep learning models develop such phenomena, then the brain likely does so as well. In that case, preventing the same from happening with deep learning models could be disastrous, if optimization demon formation turns out to be a key component in the mechanistic processes that underlie human value formation[10].
Another poster (ironically using the handle "DaemonicSigil") then found a scenario in which gradient descent does form an optimization demon. However, the scenario in question is extremely unnatural, and not at all like those found in normal deep learning practice. So no one knew whether this represented a valid "proof of concept" that realistic deep learning systems would develop optimization demons.
Roughly two and a half years later, Ulisse Mini would make DaemonicSigil's scenario a bit more like those found in deep learning by increasing the number of dimensions from 16 to 1000 (still vastly smaller than any realistic deep learning system), which produced very different results, and weakly suggested that more dimensions do reduce demon formation.
In the end, different people interpreted these results differently. We didn't get a clear, computer security-style "break" of gradient descent showing it would produce optimization demons in real-world conditions, much less that those demons would be bad for alignment. Such outcomes are very typical in alignment research.
Alignment research operates with very different epistemic feedback loops as compared to computer security. There's little reason to think the belief formation and expert identification mechanisms that arose in computer security are appropriate for alignment.
Conclusion
I hope I've been able to show that there are informed, concrete arguments for optimism, that do engage with the details of pessimistic arguments. Alignment is an incredibly diverse field. Alignment researchers vary widely in their estimated odds of catastrophe. Yudkowsky is on the extreme-pessimism end of the spectrum, for what I think are mostly invalid reasons.
Thanks to Steven Byrnes and Alex Turner for comments and feedback on this post.
- ^
By this, I mostly mean the sorts of empirical approaches we actually use on current state of the art language models, such as RLHF, red teaming, etc.
- ^
We can take drugs, though, which maybe does something like change the brain's learning rate, or some other hyperparameters.
- ^
Technically it's trained to do decision transformer-esque reward-conditioned generation of texts.
- ^
The brain likely includes within-neuron learnable parameters, but I expect these to be a relatively small contribution to the overall information content a human accumulates over their lifetime. For convenience, I just say “connectome” in the main text, but really I mean “connectome + all other within-lifetime learnable parameters of the brain’s operation”.
- ^
I expect there are pretty straightforward ways of leveraging a 99% successful alignment method into a near-100% successful method by e.g., ensembling multiple training runs, having different runs cross-check each other, searching for inputs that lead to different behaviors between different models, transplanting parts of one model's activations into another model and seeing if the recipient model becomes less aligned, etc.
- ^
Some alignment researchers do argue that gradient descent is likely to create such an intelligence - an inner optimizer - that then deliberately manipulates the training process to its own ends. I don't believe this either. I don't want to dive deeply into my objections to that bundle of claims in this post, but as with Yudkowsky's position, I have many technical objections to such arguments. Briefly, they:
- often rely on inappropriate analogies to evolution.
- rely on unproven (and dubious, IMO) claims about the inductive biases of gradient descent.
- rely on shaky notions of "optimization" that lead to absurd conclusions when critically examined.
- seem inconsistent with what we know of neural network internal structures (they're very interchangeable and parallel).
- seem like the postulated network structure would fall victim to internally generated adversarial examples.
- don't track the distinction between mesa objectives and behavioral objectives (one can probably convert an NN into an energy function, then parameterize the NN's forwards pass as a search for energy function minima, without changing network behavior at all, so mesa objectives can have ~no relation to behavioral objectives).
- seem very implausible when considered in the context of the human learning process (could a human's visual cortex become "deceptively aligned" to the objective of modeling their visual field?).
- provide limited avenues for any such inner optimizer to actually influence the training process.
See also: Deceptive Alignment is <1% Likely by Default - ^
There's also in-context learning, which arguably does count as 'getting smarter while running in inference mode'. E.g., without updating any weights, LMs can:
- adapt information found in task descriptions / instructions to solving future task instances.
- given a coding task, write an initial plan on how to do that task, and then use that plan to do better on the coding task in question.
- even learn to classify images.
The reason this in-context learning doesn't always lead to persistent improvements (or at least changes) in GPT-4 is because OpenAI doesn't train their models like that. - ^
OpenAI does periodically train its models in a way that incorporates user inputs somehow. E.g., ChatGPT became much harder to jailbreak after OpenAI trained against the breaks people used against it. So GPT-4 is probably learning from some of the times it's run in inference mode.
- ^
Unless we actually try the approach and it fails in the way predicted. But that hasn't happened (yet).
- ^
This sentence would sound much less weird if John had called them "attractors" instead of "demons". One potential downside of choosing evocative names for things is that they can make it awkward to talk about those things in an emotionally neutral way.
- ^
The brain likely includes within-neuron learnable parameters, but I expect these to be a relatively small contribution to the overall information content a human accumulates over their lifetime. For convenience, I just say “connectome” in the main text, but really I mean “connectome + all other within-lifetime learnable parameters of the brain’s operation”.
I have a lot of responses to specific points; I'm going to make them as children comment to this comment.
uh
is your proposal "use the true reward function, and then you won't get misaligned AI"?
These three paragraphs feel incoherent to me. The human eating ice cream and activating their reward circuits is exactly what you would expect under the current para... (read more)
This seems... like a correct description but it's missing the spirit?
Like the intuitions are primarily about "what features are salient" and "what thoughts are easy to think."
Roughly, the core distinction between software engineering and computer security is whether the system is thinking back. Software engineering typically involves working with dynamic systems and thinking optimistically how the system could work. Computer security typically involves working with reactive systems and thinking pessimistically about how the system could break.
I think it is an extremely basic AI alignment skill to look at your alignment proposal and ask "how does this break?" or "what happens if the AI thinks about this?".
... (read more)I do think this is a point against Yudkowsky. That said, my impression is that GANs are finicky, and I heard rumors that many people tried similar ideas and failed to get it to work before Goodfellow knocked it out of the park. If people were encouraged to publish negative results, we might have a better sense of the actual landscape here, but I think a story of "Goodfellow was unusually good at making GANs and this is why he got it right on his first try" is more compelling to me than "GANs were easy actually".
I don't yet understand why you put misgeneralized in scare quotes, or whether you have a story for why it's a misgeneralization instead of things working as expected.
I think your story for why humans like ice cream makes sense, and is basically the story Yudkowsky would tell too, with one exception:
"such food sources" feels a little like it's eliding the distinction between "high-quality food sources of the ancestral environment" and "foods like ice cream"; the training dataset couldn't differentiate between functions
f
andg
but those functions differ in their reaction to the test set (ice cream). Yudkowsky's primary point with this section, as I understand it, is that even if you-as-evolution know that you wantg
the only way you can communicate that under the current learning paradigm is with training examples, and it may be non-obvious to which functionsf
need to be excluded.Do you have kids, or any experience with them? (There are three small children in the house I live in.) I think you might want to look into childproofing, and meditate on its connection to security mindset.
Yes, this isn't necessarily related to the 'values' part, but for that I would suggest things like Direct Instruction, which involves careful curriculum design to generate lots of examples so that students will reliably end up inferring the correct rule.
In short, I think the part of 'raising children' which involves the kids being intelligent as well and independently minded does benefit from security mindset.
As you mention in the next paragraph, this is a long-standing disagreement; I might as well point at the discussion of the relevance of raising human children to instilling goals in an AI in The Detached Lever Fallacy. The short summary of it is that humans have a wide range of options for their 'values', and are running some strategy of learning from their environment (including their parents and their style of raising children) which values ... (read more)
I think you're basically misunderstanding and misrepresenting Yudkowsky's argument from 2008. He's not saying "you can't make an AI out of neural networks", he's saying "your design sharing a single feature with the brain does not mean it will also share the brain's intelligence." As well, I don't think he's arguing about how AI will actually get made; I think he's mostly criticizing the actual AGI developers/enthusiasts that he saw at the time (who were substantially less intelligent and capable than the modern batch of AGI developers).
I think that post has held up pretty well. The architectures used to organize neural networks are quite important, not just the base element. Someone whose only plan was to make their ANN wide would not reach AGI; they needed to do something else, that didn't just rely on surface analogies.
I disagree with much of what you say here, but I'm happy to see such a thorough point by point object-level response! Thanks!
Some arguments which Eliezer advanced in order to dismiss neural networks,[1] seem similar to some reasoning which he deploys in his modern alignment arguments.
Compare his incorrect mockery from 2008:
with his claim in Alexander and Yudkowsky on AGI goals:
... (read more)I don't really get your comment. Here are some things I don't get:
Actually the wright brother's central innovation and the centerpiece of the later aviation patent wars - wing warping based flight control - was literally directly copied from birds. It involved just about zero aerodynamics calculations. Moreover their process didn't involve much "calculation" in general; they downloaded a library of existing flyer designs from the smithsonian and then developed a wind tunnel to test said designs at high throughput before selecting a few for full-scale physical prototypes. Their process was light on formal theory and heavy on experimentation.
At the time the wright brothers entered the race there were many successful glider designs already, and it was fairly obvious to many that one could build a powered flyer by attaching an engine to a glider. The two key challenges were thrust to weight ratio and control. Overcoming the first obstacle was mostly a matter of timing due to exploit the rapid improvements in IC engines, while nobody really had good ideas for control yet. Competitors were exploring everything from "sky railroads" (airplanes on fixed flight tracks with zero control) to the obvious naval ship-like pure rudder control (which doesn't work well).
So the wright brothers already had confidence their plane would fly before even entering the race, if by "fly" we only mean in the weak aerodynamic sense of "it's possible to stay aloft". But for true powered controlled flight - it is exactly similarity to birds that gave them confidence as avian flight control is literally the source of their key innovation.
Why do you think the confidence came from this and not from the fact that
?
I don't think this is a fair reading of Yudkowsky. He was dismissing people who were impressed by the analogy between ANNs and the brain. I'm pretty sure it wasn't supposed to be a positive claim that ANNs wouldn't work. Rather, it's that one couldn't justifiably believe that they'd work just from the brain analogy, and that if they did work, that would be bad news for what he then called Friendliness (because he was hoping to discover and wield a "clean" theory of intelligence, as contrasted to evolution or gradient descent happening to get there at sufficient scale).
Consider "Artificial Mysterious Intelligence" (2008). In response to someone who said "But neural networks are so wonderful! They solve problems and we don't have any idea how they do it!", it's significant that Yudkowsky's reply wasn't, "No, they don't" (contesting the capabilities claim), but rather, "If you don't know how your AI works, that is not good. It is bad" (asserting that opaque capabilities are bad for alignment).
One of Yudkowsky's claims in the post you link is:
This is a claim that lack of the correct mechanistic theory is a formidable barrier for capabilities, not just alignment, and it inaccurately underestimates the amount of empirical understandings available on which to base an empirical approach.
It's true that it's hard, even perhaps impossible, to build a flying machine if the only thing you understand is that birds "magically" fly.
But if you are like most people for thousands of years, you've observed many types of things flying, gliding, or floating in the air: birds and insects, fabric and leaves, arrows and spears, clouds and smoke.
So if you, like the Montgolfier brothers, observe fabric floating over a fire, and live in an era in which invention is celebrated and have the ability to build, test, and iterate, then you can probably figure out how to build a flying machine without basing this on a fully worked out concept of aerodyna... (read more)
Another possibility is that at least some people do have a deep mechanistic understanding of how intelligence works, and that's why they are able to build deep learning systems that ultimately work. Some of the theories of how DL works might be true, and they might be more sophisticated than we are giving credit.
If that were the case, I actually would fault Eliezer, at least a little. He’s frequently, though by no means always, stuck to qualitative and hard-to-pin-down punditry like we see here, rather than to unambiguous forecasting.
This allows him, or his defenders, to retroactively defend his predictions as somehow correct even when they seem wrong in hindsight.
Let’s imagine for a moment that Eliezer’s right that AI safety is a cosmically important issue, and yet that he’s quite mistaken about all the technical details of how AGI will arise and how to effectively make it safe. It would be important to know whether we can trust his judgment and leadership.
Without the ability to evaluate his performance, either by going with the most obvious interpretation of his qualitative judgments or an unambiguous forecast, it’s hard to evaluate his performance as an AI safety leader. Combine that with a culture of deference to perceived expertise and status and the problem gets worse.
So I prioritize the avoidance of special pleading in this case: I think Eliezer comes across as clearly wrong in substance in this specific post, and that it’s important not to reach for ways “he was actually right from... (read more)
I also don't really get your position. You say that,
but you haven't shown this!
In Surface Analogies and Deep Causes, I read him as saying that neural networks don't automatically yield intelligence just because they share surface similarities with the brain. This is clearly true; at the very least, using token-prediction (which is a task for which (a) lots of training data exist and (b) lots of competence in many different domains is helpful) is a second requirement. If you take the network of GPT-4 and trained it to play chess instead, you won't get something with cross-domain competence.
In Failure by Analogy he makes a very similar abstract point -- and wrt to neural networks in particular, he says that the surface similarity to the brain is a bad reason to be confident in them. This also seems true. Do you really think that neural networks work because they are similar to brains on the surface?
You also said,
But Eliezer says this too in the post you li... (read more)
Responding to part of your comment:
I know he's talking about alignment, and I'm criticizing that extremely strong claim. This is the main thing I wanted to criticize in my comment! I think the reasoning he presents is not much supported by his publicly available arguments.
That claim seems to be advanced due to... there not being enough similarities between ANNs and human brains -- that without enough similarity in mechanisms wich were selected for by evolution, you simply can't get the AI to generalize in the mentioned human-like way. Not as a matter of the AI's substrate, but as a matter of the AI's policy not generalizing like that.
I think this is a dubious claim, and it's made based off of analogies to evolution / some unknown importance of having evolution-selected mechanisms which guide value formation (and not SGD-based mechanisms).
From the Alexander/Yudkowsky debate:
... (read more)Here's another attempt at one of my contentions.
Consider shard theory of human values. The point of shard theory is not "because humans do RL, and have nice properties, therefore AI + RL will have nice properties." The point is more "by critically examining RL + evidence from humans, I have hypotheses about the mechanistic load-bearing components of e.g. local-update credit assignment in a bounded-compute environment on certain kinds of sensory data, that these components leads to certain exploration/learning dynamics, which explain some portion of human values and experience. Let's test that and see if the generators are similar."
And my model of Eliezer shakes his head at the naivete of expecting complex human properties to reproduce outside of human minds themselves, because AI is not human.
But then I'm like "this other time you said 'AI is not human, stop expecting good property P from superficial similarities', you accidentally missed the modern AI revolution, right? Seems like there is some non-superficial mechanistic similarity/lessons here, and we shouldn't be so quick to assume that the brain's qualitative intelligence or alignment properties come from a huge number of evolutionarily-tuned details which are load-bearing and critical."
Another way of putting it:
If you can effortlessly find an empirical pattern that shows up over and over again in disparate flying things - birds and insects, fabric and leaves, clouds and smoke and sparks - and which do not consistently show up in non-flying things, then you can be very confident it's not a coincidence. If you have at least some ability to engineer a model to play with the mechanisms you think might be at work, even better. That pattern you have identified is almost certainly a viable general mechanism for flight.
Likewise, if you can effortlessly find an empirical pattern that shows up over and over again in disparate intelligent things, you can be quite confident that the pattern is a key for intelligence. Animals have a wide variety of brain structures, but masses of interconnected neurons are common to all of them, and we could see possible precursors to intelligence in neural nets long before gpt-2 to -4.
As a note, just because you've found a viable mechanism for X doesn't mean it's the only, best, or most comprehensive mechanism for X. Balloons have been largely superceded (though I've heard zeppelins proposed as a new form of cargo transport), airplanes and h... (read more)
It now seems clear to me that EY was not bullish on neural networks leading to impressive AI capabilities. Eliezer said this directly:
I think this is strong evidence for my interpretation of the quotes in my parent comment: He's not just mocking the local invalidity of reasoning "because humans have lots of neurons, AI with lots of neurons -> smart", he's also mocking neural network-driven hopes themselves.
- ^
... (read more)More quotes from Logical or Connectionist AI?:
In this passage, he employs well-s
How do humans learn "don't steal" rather than "don't get caught"? I wonder if the answer to this question could solve the alignment problem. In other words, this question might be a good crux.
In answering this question, the first thing we can notice is that humans don't always learn "don't steal". That is to say, sometimes humans do steal, and a good part of human culture is built around impeding or punishing humans who learned the wrong lesson in kindergarten. It is an old debate whether humans are mostly good with the occasional bad actor (with "bad actors" possibly being good people in a bad situation), or whether humans are mostly bad and need to be controlled by a powerful state, or God etc.
A modern consensus view is that humans are mostly good, but if we didn't impede or punish bad actors, we would get bad outcomes (total anarchy doesn't work). If we assume that there are many AGIs and they have a similar distribution of good and bad, and that no AGI is more powerful than typical human today (in particular no AGI is uncontrollable), then in this scenario we can rest easy. Law and order works reasonably well for humans, and should work just fine for human-level AGIs.
The proble... (read more)
At a high level, I'm sort of confused by why you're choosing to respond to the extremely simplified presentation of Eliezer's arguments that he presented in this podcast.
I do also have some object-level thoughts.
But not only do current implementations of RLHF not manage to robustly enforce the desired external behavior of models that would be necessary to make versions scaled up to superintellegence safe, we have approximately no idea what sort of internal cognition they generate as a pathway to those behaviors. (I have a further objection to your argument about dimensionality which I'll address below.)
... (read more)Before writing this post, I was working a post explaining why I thought all the arguments for doom I've ever heard (from Yudkowsky or others) seemed flawed to me. I kept getting discouraged because there are so many arguments to cover, and it probably would have been ~3 or more times longer than this post. Responding just to the arguments Yudkowsky raised in the podcast helped me to focus actually get something out in a reasonable timeframe.
There will always be more arguments I could have included (maybe about convergent consequentialism, utility theory, the limits of data-constrained generalization, plausible constraints on takeoff speed, the feasibility of bootstrapping nanotech, etc), but the post was already > 9,000 words.
I also don't think Yudkowsky's arguments in the podcast were all that simplified. E.g., here he is in List of Lethalities on evolution / inner alignment:
... (read more)I think I've been in situations where I've been disoriented by a bunch of random stuff happening and wished that less of it was happening so that I could get a better handle on stuff. An example I vividly recall was being in a history class in high school and being very bothered by the large number of conversations happening around me.
I narrowly agree with most of this, but I tend to say the same thing with a very different attitude:
I would say: “Gee it would be super cool if we could decide a priori what we want the AGI to be trying to do, WITH SURGICAL PRECISION. But alas, that doesn’t seem possible, at least not according to any method I know of.”
I disagree with you in your apparent suggestion that the above paragraph is obvious or uninteresting, and also disagree with your apparent suggestion that “setting an AGI’s motivations with surgical precision” is such a dumb idea that we shouldn’t even waste one minute of our time thinking about whether it might be possible to do that.
For ... (read more)
Your first objection seems utterly unconvincing to me because you go...
... and then list off a bunch of approaches that seem more naive than scary.
There's definitely lots of bad approaches out there! But that doesn't mean your preferred approach will be the final one.
I think there's a mistake here which kind of invalidates the whole post. If we don't reward our AI for taking bad actions within the training distribution, it's still very possible that in the future world, looking quite unlike the training distribution, the AI will be able to find such an action. Same as ice cream wasn't in evolution's training distribution for us, but then we found it anyway.
I'm sympathetic to some of your arguments but even if we accept that the current paradigm will lead us to an AI that is pretty similar to a human mind, and even in the best case I'm already not super optimistic that a scaled up random almost human is a great outcome. I simply disagree where you say this:
>For example, humans are not perfectly robust. I claim that for any human, no matter how moral, there exist adversarial sensory inputs that would cause them to act badly. Such inputs might involve extreme pain, starvation, exhaustion, etc. I don't think the mere existence of such inputs means that all humans are unaligned.
Humans aren't that aligned at the extreme and the extreme matters when talking about the smartest entity making every important decision about everything.
Also, your general arguments about the current paradigms being not that bad are reasonable but again, I think our situation is a lot closer to all or nothing - if we get pretty far with RLHF or whatever, scale up the model until it's extremely smart and thus eventually making every decision of consequence then unless you got the alignment near perfectly the chance that the remaining problematic parts screw us over seems uncomfortably high to me.
GPT4's tentative summary:
Section 1: Summary
The article critiques Eliezer Yudkowsky's pessimistic views on AI alignment and the scalability of current AI capabilities. The author argues that AI progress will be smoother and integrate well with current alignment techniques, rather than rendering them useless. They also believe that humans are more general learners than Yudkowsky suggests, and the space of possible mind designs is smaller and more compact. The author challenges Yudkowsky's use of the security mindset, arguing that AI alignment should not be approached as an adversarial problem.
Section 2: Underlying Arguments and Examples
1. Scalability of current AI capabilities paradigm:
- Various clever capabilities approaches, such as meta-learning, learned optimizers, and simulated evolution, haven't succeeded as well as the current paradigm.
- The author expects that future capabilities advances will integrate well with current alignment techniques, seeing issues as "ordinary engineering challenges" and expecting smooth progress.
2. Human generality:
- Humans have a general learning process that can adapt to new environments, with powerful cognition arising from s... (read more)
What stood out to me in the video is Eliezer no longer being able to conceive of any positive outcome at all, which is beyond reason. It made me wonder what approach a company could possible develop for alignment, or what a supposedly aligned AI could possibly do, for Eliezer to take back his doom predictions, and suspect that the answer is none. The impression I got was that he is meanwhile closed to the possibility entirely. I found the Time article heartbreaking. These are parents, intelligent, rational parents who I have respect and compassion for, ess... (read more)
Strongly upvoted!
I endorse the entirety of this post, and if anything I hold some objections/reservations more strongly than you have presented them here[1].
I very much appreciate that you have grounded these objections firmly in the theory and practice of modern machine learning.
In particular, Yudkowsky's claim that a superintelligence is efficient wrt humanity on all cognitive tasks is IMO flat out infeasible/unattainable (insomuch as we include human aligned technology when evaluating the capabilities of humanity). ↩︎
n=1, but I've actually thought this before.
Very interesting write up. Do you have a high level overview of why, despite all of this, P(doom) is still 5%? What do you still see as the worst failure modes?
But some of the most impactful are - law making, economics and various others where one ought to think about incentives, "other side", or doing pre-mortems. Perhaps this could be stretched as far as "security mindset is an invaluable part of a rationality toolbox".
... (read more)Discussion of human generality.
It should be named Discussion of "human generality versus Artificial General Intelligence generality". And there is exist example of human generality much closer to 'okay, let me just go reprogram myself a bit, and then I'll be as adapted to this thing as I am to' which is not "i am going to read a book or 10 on this topic" but "i am going to meditate for couple of weeks to change my reward circuitry so i will be as interested in coding after as i am interested in doing all side quests in Witcher 3 now"and "i as a human have ... (read more)
I agree with OP th... (read more)
Accepting the idea that an AGI emerging from ML is likely to resemble a human mind more closely than a random mind from mindspace might not be an obvious reason to be less concerned with AGI risk. Consider a paperclip maximizer; despite its faults, it has no interest in torturing humans. As an AGI becomes more similar to human minds, it may become more willing to impose suffering on humans. If a random AGI mind has a 99% chance of killing us and a 1% chance of allowing us to thrive, while an ML-created AGI (not aligned with our values) has a 90% chance of ... (read more)
This post brought to mind a thought: I actually don't care very much about arguments about how likely doom is and how pessimistic or optimistic to be since they are irrelevant, to my style of thinking, for making decisions related to building TAI. Instead, I mostly focus on downside risks and avoiding them because they are so extreme, which makes me look "pessimistic" but actually I'm just trying to minimize the risk of false positives in building aligned AI. Given this framing, it's actually less important, in most cases, to figure out how likely somethin... (read more)
Possibly yes. I could easily see this underlying human preferences for regular patterns in art. Predictable enough to get a high score, not so predictable that whatever secondary boredom mechanism that keeps baby humans from maximising score by staring straight at the ceiling all day kicks in. I'm even getting suspiciou... (read more)
This also makes a lot of sense intuitively, as it should become more difficult in higher dimensions to construct walls (hills / barriers without holes).
On Yudkowsky and being wrong:
I'm going to be careful about reading in to his words too much, and assuming he said something that I disagree with.
But I have noticed and do notice a tendency towards pessimism and pessimists in general to prefer beliefs that skew towards "wrongness" and "incorrectness" and "mistake-making" that tends to be borderline-superstitious. The superstitious-ness I refer to regards the tendency to give errors higher-status than they deserve, e.g., by predicting things to go wrong, in order for them to be less likely to go wrong,... (read more)
The post answers the first question "Will current approaches scale to AGI?" in the affirmative and then seems to run with that.
I think the post makes a good case that Yudkowsky's pessimism is not applicable to AIs built with current architectures and scaled-up versions of current architectures.
But it doesn't address the following cases:
I believe for these cases, Yudkowsky's arguments and pessi... (read more)
Nitpick: That doesn't seem like what you would expect. Arguably I have very little conscious access to the part of my brain predicting what I will see next, and the optimization of that part is probably independent of the optimization that happens in the more conscious parts of my brain.
I think you could defend a stronger claim (albeit you'd have to expend some effort): misgeneralisation of this kind is a predictable consequence of the evolution "training paradigm", and would in fact be predicted by machine learning practitioners. I think the fact that the failure is soft (humans don't eat ice cream until they die) might be harder to predict than the fact that the failure occurs.
... (read more)The more I think about it, the less am I convinced the overgeneralisation problem will play out the way it is feared here when it comes to AI alignment.
Let's take Eliezers example. Evolution wants humans to optimise for producing more humans. It does so by making humans want sex. This works quite well. It also produces humans that are smarter, and this turns out to also be a good way to get higher reproduction rates, as they are better at obtaining food and impressing mates.
But then, a bunch of really smart humans go, man, we like having sex, but hav... (read more)
"discovering that you're wrong about something should, in expectation, reduce your confidence in X"
This logic seems flawed. Suppose X is whether humans go extinctinct. You have an estimate of the distribution of X (for a bernoulli process it would be some probability p). Take the joint distribution of X and the factors on which X depends (p is now a function of those factors). Your best estimate of p is the mean of the joint distribution and the variance measures how uncertain you're about the factors. Discovering that you're wrong about something means be... (read more)
I think you're misreading Eliezer here. "Duplicate this strawberry" is just a particular task instruction. The value system is "don't destroy the world as a side effect."
Upvoted mainly for the 'width of mindspace' section. The general shard theory worldview makes a lot more sense to me after reading that.
Consider a standalone post on that topic if there isn't one already.
Difficulty of Alignment
I find the prospect of training on model on just 40 parameters to be very interesting. Almost unbelievable, really, to the point where I'm tempted to say: "I notice that I'm confused". Unfortunately, I don't have access to the paper and it doesn't seem to be on sci-hub, so I haven't been able to resolve my confusion. Basically, my general intuition is that each parameter in a network probably only contributes a few bits of optimization power. It can be set fairly high, fairly low, or in between. So if you just pulled 40 random weigh... (read more)
Another example may be lactose tolerance. First you need animal husbandry and dairy production, then you get selective pressure favoring those who can reliably process lactose, without the "concept of husbandry" there's no way for the optimizer to select for it.
I'm much less STEM-oriented than most people here, so I could just be totally misunderstanding the points made in this post, but I tried reading it anyway, and a couple of things stood out to me as possibly mistaken:
Am I missing something here, or is this just describing memetics? Granted, skills, knowledge, values, traditions, etc., are heritable in other w... (read more)
Just listened to the video, and I immediately understood his rocket argument very differently from yours. With a potential rocket crash representing launching AGI without alignment with the resulting existential risk, and Eliezer expressing concerns that we cannot steer the rocket well enough before launch. And the main point being that a rocket launch being a success is a very asymmetrical situation when it comes to the impact of mistakes on results.
As I understood the argument it is:
- A bunch of people build a spacecraft.
- Eliezer says based on argument ABC,
... (read more)Possibly-relevant resource: the Stampy.ai site.
The following is not a very productive comment, but...
I think this section detracts from your post, or at least the heading seems off. Yudkowsky hedges as making a "very primitive, very basic, very unreliable wild guess" and your response is about how you think the guess is wrong. I agree that the guess is likely to be wrong. I expect Yudkowsky agrees, given his hedging.
Insofar as we are going to make any guesses about what goals our models have, "predict humans really well" or "predict n... (read more)
I think the proper narrative in the rocket alignment post is "We have cannons and airplanes. Now, how do we land a man on the Moon", not just "rocketry is hard":
So, the failure modes look less like "we misplaced booster tank and the thing exploded" and more like "we've built a huge-ass rocket, but it missed its objective and the astronauts are en-route to Oort's".
My only objection is the title. It should have a comma in it. "We’re All Gonna Die with Eliezer Yudkowsky" makes it sound like if Yudkowsky dies, then all hope is lost and we die too.
Ohhh...
It can't now (or it can?). Is there no 100 robots in 100 10x10 meters labs trained with recreating all human technology from stone age and after? If it is cost less than 10 mil then they probably are. This is a joke but i don't know how offtarget it is.
This is silly because it's actually the exact opposite. Gradient descent is incredibly narrow. Natural selection is the polar opposite of that kind of optimisation: an organism or even computer can come up with a complex solution to any and every problem given enough time to e... (read more)
Haha.
This is kinda long. If I had time to engage with one part of this as a sample of whether it holds up to a counterresponse, what would be the strongest foot you could put forward?
(I also echo the commenter who's confused about why you'd reply to the obviously simplified presentation from an off-the-cuff podcast rather than the more detailed arguments elsewhere.)
This response is enraging.
Here is someone who has attempted to grapple with the intellectual content of your ideas and your response is "This is kinda long."? I shouldn't be that surprised because, IIRC, you said something similar in response to Zack Davis' essays on the Map and Territory distinction, but that's ancillary and AI is core to your memeplex.
I have heard repeated claims that people don't engage with the alignment communities' ideas (recent example from yesterday). But here is someone who did the work. Please explain why your response here does not cause people to believe there's no reason to engage with your ideas because you will brush them off. Yes, nutpicking e/accs on Twitter is much easier and probably more hedonic, but they're not convincible and Quinton here is.
I would agree with this if Eliezer had never properly engaged with critics, but he's done that extensively. I don't think there should be a norm that you have to engage with everyone, and "ok choose one point, I'll respond to that" seems like better than not engaging with it at all. (Would you have been more enraged if he hadn't commented anything?)
The problem is that the even if the model of Quintin Pope is wrong, there is other evidence that contradicts the AI doom premise that Eliezer ignores, and in this I believe it is a confirmation bias at work here.
Also, any issues with Quintin Pope's model is going to be subtle, not obvious, and it's a real difference to argue against good arguments + bad arguments from only bad arguments.
I also agree that the comment came across as rude. I mostly give Eliezer a pass for this kind of rudeness because he's wound up in the genuinely awkward position of being a well-known intellectual figure (at least in these circles), which creates a natural asymmetry between him and (most of) his critics.
I'm open to being convinced that I'm making a mistake here, but at present my view is that comments primarily concerning how Eliezer's response tugs at the social fabric (including the upthread reply from iceman) are generally unproductive.
(Quentin, to his credit, responded by directly answering Eliezer's question, and indeed the resulting (short) thread seems to have resulted in some clarification. I have a lot more respect for that kind of object-level response, than I do for responses along the lines of iceman's reply.)
Choosing to engage with an unscripted unrehearsed off-the-cuff podcast intended to introduce ideas to a lay audience, continues to be a surprising concept to me. To grapple with the intellectual content of my ideas, consider picking one item from "A List of Lethalities" and engaging with that.
I actually did exactly this in a previous post, Evolution is a bad analogy for AGI: inner alignment, where I quoted number 16 from A List of Lethalities:
and explained why I didn't think we should put much weight on the evolution analogy when thinking about AI.
In the 7 months since I made that post, it's had < 5% of the comments engagement that this post has gotten in a day.
¯\_(ツ)_/¯
Popular and off-the-cuff presentations often get discussed because it is fun to talk about how the off-the-cuff presentation has various flaws. Most comments get generated by demon threads and scissor statements, sadly. We've done some things to combat that, and definitely not all threads with lots of comments are the result of people being slightly triggered and misunderstanding each other, but a quite substantial fraction are.
Here are some of my disagreements with List of Lethalities. I'll quote item one:
I imagine (edit: wrongly) it was less "choosing" and more "he encountered the podcast first because it has a vastly larger audience, and had thoughts about it."
I also doubt "just engage with X" was an available action. The podcast transcript doesn't mention List of Lethalities, LessWrong, or the Sequences, so how is a listener supposed to find it?
I also hate it when people don't engage with the strongest form of my work, and wouldn't consider myself obligated to respond if they engaged with a weaker form (or if they engaged with the strongest one, barring additional obligation). But I think this is just what happens when someone goes on a podcast aimed at audiences that don't already know them.
I agree with this heuristic in general, but will observe Quintin's first post here was over two years ago and he commented on A List of Lethalities; I do think it'd be fair for him to respond with "what do you think this post was?".
Vaniver is right. Note that I did specifically describe myself as an "alignment insider" at the start of this post. I've read A List of Lethalities and lots of other writing by Yudkowsky. Though the post I'd cite in response to the "you're not engaging with the strongest forms of my argument" claim would be the one where I pretty much did what Yudkowsky suggests:
My post Evolution is a bad analogy for AGI: inner alignment specifically addresses List of Lethalities point 16:
and then argues that we shouldn'... (read more)
The comment enrages me too, but the reasons you have given seem like post-justification. The real reason why it's enraging is that it rudely and dramatically implies that Eliezer's time is much more valuable than the OP's, and that it's up to OP to summarize them for him. If he actually wanted to ask OP what the strongest point was he should have just DMed him instead of engineering this public spectacle.
I want people to not discuss things in DMs, and discuss things publicly more. I also don't think this is embarrassing for Quintin, or at all a public spectacle.
The "strongest" foot I could put forwards is my response to "On current AI not being self-improving:", where I'm pretty sure you're just wrong.
However, I'd be most interested in hearing your response to the parts of this post that are about analogies to evolution, and why they're not that informative for alignment, which start at:
and end at:
However, the discussion of evolution is much longer than the discussion on self-improvement in current AIs, so look at whichever you feel you have time for.
I'll admit it straight up did not occur to me that you could possibly be analogizing between a human's lifelong, online learning process, and a single inference run of an already trained model. Those are just completely different things in my ontology.
Anyways, thank you for your response. I actually do think it helped clarify your perspective for me.
Edit: I have now included Yudkowsky's correction of his intent in the post, as well as an explanation of why I think his corrected argument is still wrong.
I think you should use a manifold market to decide on whether you should read the post, instead of the test this comment is putting forth. There's too much noise here, which isn't present in a prediction market about the outcome of your engagement.
Market here: https://manifold.markets/GarrettBaker/will-eliezer-think-there-was-a-sign
Well, this is insanely disappointing. Yes, the OP shouldn't have directly replied to the Bankless podcast like that, but it's not like he didn't read your List of Lethalities, or your other writing on AGI risk. You really have no excuse for brushing off very thorough and honest criticism such as this, particularly the sections that talk about alignment.
And as others have noted, Eliezer Yudkowsky, of all people, complaining about a blog post being long is the height of irony.
This is coming from someone who's mostly agreed with you on AGI risk since reading the Sequences, years ago, and who's donated to MIRI, by the way.
On the bright side, this does make me (slightly) update my probability of doom downwards.
Is the overall karma for this mostly just people boosting it for visibility? Because I don't see how this would be a quality comment by any other standards.
Frontpage comment guidelines:
Eliezer, in the world of AI safety, there are two separate conversations: the development of theory and observation, and whatever's hot in public conversation.
A professional AI safety researcher, hopefully, is mainly developing theory and observation.
However, we have a whole rationalist and EA community, and now a wider lay audience, who are mainly learning of and tracking these matters through the public conversation. It is the ideas and expressions of major AI safety communicators, of whom you are perhaps the most prominent, that will enter their heads. The arguments lay audiences carry may not be fully informed, but they can be influential, both on the decisions they make and the influence they bring to bear on the topic. When you get on a podcast and make off-the-cuff remarks about ideas you've been considering for a long time, you're engaging in public conversation, not developing theory and observation. When somebody critiques your presentation on the podcast, they are doing the same.
The utility of Quintin choosing to address the arguments you have chosen to put forth, off-the-cuff, to that lay audience is similar to the utility you achieve by making them in the first place. ... (read more)
I'm going to have to read through this because I think 5% is way too low.